The reader will notice a certain asymmetry in the argument. We are
weighing two things in the balance; the same term occurs on both sides
of the equation, 'other people's testimony:'
"The maxim, by which we commonly conduct ourselves in
our reasonings, is, that the objects, of which we have no
experience, resemble those, of which we have; that what we have
found to be most usual is always most probable; and that where there
is an opposition of argument, we ought to give the preference to
such as are founded on the greatest number of past observations."
(David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Section X Of
Miracles, Chapter 93.)
"[P]ast observations" conducted by whom; by ourselves? No, by
Other People. Worse, we have not ourselves gone and conducted a poll
of all these people, past and present; rather, we have been told
that other people say that. Legal thinking has traditionally sorted
testimony into several different bins, depending on whether it is
first-hand, eye-witness testimony, or whether it is second-hard
hearsay. On the Hume Express, we are not yet consistently doing that, which raises a red
flag; rather we are tossing apples into the bin with oranges.
It seems at times that we are going to count heads:
"It is experience only, which gives authority to human
testimony; and it is the same experience, which assures us of the
laws of nature. When, therefore, these two kinds of experience are
contrary, we have nothing to but subtract the one from the other,
and embrace an opinion, either on one side or the other, with the
assurance which arises from the remainder." (David Hume, An Enquiry
Concerning Human Understanding, Section X Of Miracles, Chapter 98).
Simply counting heads, I reflect that I have heard more people
say, 'He is risen indeed,' then I have ever attended funerals and
noted that the deceased did not climb up out of the coffin. While
this great cloud of witnesses may testify, 'He lives within my
heart,' they do not count as eye-witnesses in the same sense as were the
"above five hundred brethren" of 1 Corinthians 15:6.
However, if we demand the same restriction to the other side of the
equation, my personal experience of dead men failing to rise from
the grave is based on an extremely small sample. So we augment it:
with what?— hearsay, what other people say. Not 'He is risen
indeed,' but 'No one has ever seen a dead man rise,' a fact not in
the speaker's experience, unless we are hearing the massed voice of
every man, woman and child who has ever lived, a voice as of many
waters.
Other people's testimony, on one side of the equation, is counted
ultimately for nothing; yet other people's testimony, on the other
side of the equation, provides us with a magic window into the
world; it is simply the way the world is. How, after all, do we know
it never happens that a man rises from the dead? Did we learn this
from observations conducted at the handful of funerals we ourselves
have attended, or are we juicing the results with hearsay, what
other people have told us? A row of zeroes adds up to zero, after
all. And how, after all, do we arrive at our skepticism of other
people's testimony? Because other people have told us to be
skeptical of other people's testimony. Realizing this becomes a hall
of mirrors, Hume wants to toss us back upon our own experience of
the reliability of other people's testimony, which assumes we
possess means to check their testimony by our own personal
inspection, which we generally do not. Perhaps some people's
testimony has conflicted with other people's testimony.
Shall we stroll into the hall of mirrors, doesn't it look
inviting? Hume does make an effort to separate the sheep from the
goats, the Other People whose testimony we choose to discount from
the Other People whose testimony seals the deal that a man cannot rise from
the dead. It is however simply intolerable. Guess what: it's based on social
status. Can anyone seriously claim the apostles' eye-witness testimony should
be discounted because they were not socially prominent? Justice is no respecter
of persons, as we learn in the Bible; the poor man's testimony cannot
be discarded simply because he is poor. Often in front of Western
court-houses a sculptured lady is placed, wearing a blind-fold over
her eyes. She is supposed not to notice Hume's criteria, as to the
"credit and reputation in the eyes of mankind" of our witnesses, or
whether they live in a "so celebrated a part of the world." She is
not supposed to let the blind-fold slip and notice that stuff, which are markers for social status, so
why should we? The lack of any pertinent first century evidence against the
resurrection, like a body, is simply because the right sort of folks,
persons of quality, had not yet deigned to notice this new sect:
"In the infancy of new religions, the wise and learned
commonly esteem the matter too inconsiderable to deserve their
attention or regard. And when afterwards they would willingly detect
the cheat, in order to undeceive the deluded multitude, the season
is now past, and the records and witnesses, which might clear up the
matter, have perished beyond recovery." (David Hume, An Enquiry
Concerning Human Understanding, Section X Of Miracles, Chapter 97).
"[P]erished beyond recovery"; well, isn't that a shame. This argument: that the wrong kind of people witness
miracles, whereas the right kind despise them, is not worthy of serious
consideration.
Notice further that Hume's argument against miracles would destroy, not only the church's
miracles, but much of modern 'science' as it is practiced today. Quite
frankly, Hume's broom would sweep out a good bit of rubbish,
unfortunately alongside of good things like the Big Bang. Modern
evolutionary biology purports to tell the story, based on various lines
of evidence, of one-time, non-repeatable events. These events are
conceded to be inherently unlikely; we have not ourselves seen them, nor
could produce them at all. In David Hume's terms, we have no warrant for
believing in these events; we judge what happened in the past only by
what commonly happens today.
|