XENOPHON’S
MEMORABILIA OF SOCRATES
BOOK III
CHAPTER I
Socrates used to exhort those who aspired to public offices to learn the
duties that would be required in them. The duties of a military commander,
and his responsibilities, sect. 1-5. He must know many things besides military
tactics, 6-11.
1. I will now show that Socrates was of great service to those who aspired to posts of honor, by rendering them attentive to the duties of the offices which they sought.
Having heard that Dionysodorus had arrived at the city, offering to teach
the art of a general, he said to one of those who were with him, whom he
observed to be desirous of obtaining that honor in the state, 2. “It is
indeed unbecoming, young man, that he who wishes to be commander of an
army in his country should neglect to learn the duties of that office when
he has an opportunity of learning them; and such a person would be far
more justly punished by his country than one who should contract to make
statues (for it), when he had not learned to make them; 3. for as the whole
state, in the perils of war, is entrusted to the care of the general, it
is likely that great advantages will occur if he act well, and great evils
if he fall into error. How, then, would not he, who neglects to learn the
duties of the office, while he is eager to be elected to it, be deservedly
punished?” By making such observations, he induced the young man to go
and learn.
4. When, after having learned, he returned to Socrates again, he began to joke upon him, saying, “Since Homer, my friends, has represented Agamemnon as dignified, does not this young man, after learning to be a general, seem to you to look more dignified than before? For as he who has learned to play the lyre is a lyrist, though he may not use the instrument, and he who has learned the art of healing is a physician, though he may not practice his art, so this youth will from henceforth be a general, though no one may elect him to command; but he who wants the proper knowledge is neither general nor physician, even though he be chosen to act as such by all the people in the world. 5. But,” he continued, “in order that we may have a better knowledge of the military art, in case any one of us should have to command a troop or company under you, tell us how he began to teach you generalship?” “He began,” replied the youth, “with the same thing with which he ended; for he taught me tactics, and nothing else.” 6. “But,” said Socrates, “how small a part of the
qualifications of a general is this! For a general must be skillful in
preparing what is necessary for war, able in securing provisions for his
troops, a man of great contrivance and activity, careful, persevering,
and sagacious; kind, and yet severe; open, yet crafty; careful of his own,
yet ready to steal from others; profuse, yet rapacious; lavish of presents,
yet eager to acquire money; cautious, yet enterprising; and many other
qualities there are, both natural and acquired, which he, who would fill
the office of general with ability, must possess. 7. It is good, indeed,
to be skilled in tactics; for a well-arranged army is very different from
a disorderly one; as stones and bricks, wood and tiles, if thrown together
in confusion, are of no use whatever; but when the stones and tiles, materials
not likely to rot or decay, are placed at the bottom and the top, and the
bricks and wood are arranged in the middle (as in building), a house, which
is a valuable piece of property, is formed.” 8. “What you have said, Socrates,”
rejoined the youth, “is an exact illustration of our practice; for in the
field of battle we must place the bravest troops in the front and rear,
and the cowardly in the middle, that they may be led on by those before
them, and pushed forward by those behind.” 9. “If indeed he has taught
you to distinguish the brave and cowardly,” rejoined Socrates, “that rule
may be of use; but if not, what profit is there in what you have learned?
for if he ordered you, in arranging a number of coins, to lay the best
first and last, and the worst in the middle, and gave you no instructions
how to distinguish the good and bad, his orders to you would be to no purpose.”
“But indeed,” he replied, “he did not teach me this; so that we must distinguish
the brave from the cowardly ourselves.” 10. “Why should we not consider
then,” said Socrates, “how we may avoid mistakes as to that matter?” “I
am willing,” returned the young man. “If then we had to capture a sum of
money, and were to place the most covetous men in front, should we not
arrange them properly?” “It appears so to me.” “And what must generals
do when entering on a perilous enterprise? Must they not place the most
ambitious in front?” “They at least,” said the young man, “are those who
are ready to brave danger for the sake of praise; and they are by no means
difficult to discover, but will be everywhere conspicuous and easy to be
selected.” 11. “But did your instructor,” inquired Socrates, “teach you
to arrange an army, merely, or did he tell you in what direction, and in
what manner, you must employ each division of your forces? “ “Not at all,”
replied he. “Yet there are many occasions, on which it is not proper to
draw up an army, or to conduct it, in the same way.” “But, by Jupiter,
he gave me no explanation as to such occasions.” “Go again, then, by all
means,” said Socrates, “and question him; for if he knows, and is not quite
shameless, he will blush, after taking your money, to send you away in
ignorance.”
CHAPTER II
A good general ought to take measures for the safety, maintenance, and
success of his troops; and not to study his own honor alone, but that of
his whole army.
1. Having met, on some occasion, a person who had been elected general,
Socrates said to him, “Why is it, do you think, that Homer has styled Agamemnon
‘Shepherd of the people’? Is it not for this reason, that as a shepherd
must be careful that his sheep be safe, and have food, so a general must
take care that his soldiers be safe, and have provisions, and that the
object be effected for which they serve? and they serve, no doubt, that
they may increase their gratifications by conquering the enemy. 2. Or why
has he praised Agamemnon in the following manner, saying that he was
Both characters, a good king, and an efficient warrior?
Does he not mean that he would not have been ‘an efficient warrior,’ if
he had fought courageously alone against the enemy, and if he had not been
the cause of courage to his whole army; and that he would not have been
‘a good king,’ if he had attended to his own subsistence only, and had
not been the cause of comfort to those over whom he ruled? 3. For a man
is chosen king, not that he may take good care of himself, but that those
who have chosen him may prosper by his means; and all men, when they take
the field, take it that their lives may be rendered as happy as possible,
and choose generals that they may conduct them to the accomplishment of
that object. 4. It is incumbent on the leader of an army, therefore, to
render this to those who have chosen him their leader. Nor is it easy to
find anything more honorable than such exertion, or more disgraceful than
an opposite course of conduct.”
Thus considering what was the merit of a good leader, he omitted other points in his character, and left only this, that he should render those whom he commanded happy.
CHAPTER III
The duty of a commander of cavalry is twofold, to improve the condition
both of his men and his horses; and not to leave the care of the horses
to the troops, sect. 1-4. How he should train his men, and how he should
be himself qualified to do so, 5-10. He should acquire oratorical power,
that he may incite his men to exertion, and fire them with the desire of
glory, 11-14.
1. I remember that he held a dialogue with a person who had been chosen
Hipparch, to the following purport. “Could you tell me, young man,” said
he, “with what object you desired to be a Hipparch? It certainly was not
for the sake of riding first among the cavalry; for the horse-archers are
honored with that dignity, as they ride even before the Hipparchs.” “You
say the truth,” said the youth. “Nor was it, surely, for the sake of being
noticed, for even madmen are noticed by everybody.” “You say the truth
in that respect also.” 2. “But was it, then, that you expect to render
the cavalry better, and present them in that condition to your country,
and that, if there should be need for the services of cavalry, you hope,
as their leader, to be the author of some advantage to the state?” “I do
hope so, certainly.” “And it will be truly honorable to you,” continued
Socrates, “if you are able to effect that object. But the command, to which
you have been chosen, takes charge of both the horses and riders?” “It
does so,” said the young man. 3. “Come, then, tell me this first of all,
how you propose to render the horses better?” “That,” replied the other,
“I do not consider to be my business; for I think that each man, individually,
must take care of his own horse.” 4. “If, then,” said Socrates, “some of
the men should present their horses before you so diseased in the feet,
so weak in the legs, or so feeble in body, and others theirs so ill-fed,
that they could not follow you; others, theirs so unmanageable, that they
would not remain where you posted them; others, theirs so vicious that
it would not he possible to post them at all; what would be the use of
such cavalry to you? Or how would you be able, at the head of them, to
be of any service to your country?” “You admonish me well,” said the youth,
“and I will try to look to the horses as far as may be in my power.” 5.
“And will you not also endeavor,” asked Socrates, “to make the riders better?”
“I will,” said he. “You will first of all, then, make them more expert
in mounting their horses.” “I ought to do so; for if any of them should
fall off, they would thus be better prepared to recover themselves.” 6.
“If, then,” said Socrates, “you should be obliged to hazard an engagement,
whether will you order your men to bring the enemy down to the level sand
on which you have been accustomed to ride, or will you try to exercise
them on such ground as that on which the enemy may show themselves?” “The
latter method will be the better,” said the young man. 7. “Will you also
take any care that the greatest possible number of your men may be able
to hurl the dart on horseback?” “That will be better too,” replied he.
“And have you considered how to whet the courage of your cavalry, which
makes them more courageous, and animate them against the enemy?” “If I
have not yet considered,” said he, “I will now try to do so.” 8. “And have
you at all considered how your cavalry may be induced to obey you? For
without obedience you will have no profit either from horses or horsemen,
spirited and valiant as they may be.” “You say the truth, Socrates,” said
he; “but by what means can a leader most effectually induce them to obedience?”
9. “You are doubtless aware that in all circumstances men most willingly
obey those whom they consider most able to direct; for in sickness patients
obey him whom they think the best physician; on ship-board, the passengers
obey him whom they think the best pilot, and in agriculture, people obey
him whom they deem the best husbandman.” “Unquestionably,” said the young
man. “Is it not then likely,” said Socrates, “that in horsemanship also,
others will be most willing to obey him who appears to know best what he
ought to do?” 10. “If, therefore, Socrates, I should myself appear the
best horseman among them, will that circumstance be sufficient to induce
them to obey me?” “If you convince them in addition,” said Socrates, “that
it is better and safer for them to obey you.” “How, then, shall I convince
them of that?” “With much more ease,” replied Socrates, “than if you had
to convince them that bad things are better and more profitable than good.”
11. “You mean,” said the young man, “that a commander of cavalry, in addition
to his other qualifications, should study to acquire some ability in speaking.”
“And did you think,” asked Socrates, “that you would command cavalry by
silence? Have you not reflected, that whatever excellent principles we
have learned according to law, principles by which we know how to live,
we learned all through the medium of speech; and that whatever other valuable
instruction any person acquires, he acquires it by means of speech likewise?
Do not those who teach best, use speech most; and those who know the most
important truths, discuss them with the greatest eloquence? 12. Or have
you not observed, that when a band of dancers and musicians is formed from
this city, as that, for instance, which is sent to Delos, no one from any
other quarter can compete with it; and that in no other city is manly grace
shown by numbers of people like that which is seen here?” “What you say
is true,” said he. 13. “But it is not so much in sweetness of voice, or
in size and strength of body, that the Athenians excel other people, as
in ambition, which is the greatest incitement to whatever is honorable
and noble.” “This also is true,” said he. 14. “Do you not think, then,”
said Socrates, “that if any one should study to improve the cavalry here,
the Athenians would excel other people in that department also (as well
in the equipment of their arms and horses as in the good order of the men,
and in boldly defying danger to encounter the enemy), if they thought that
by such means they would acquire praise and honor?” “It is probable,” said
the young man. “Do not delay, therefore,” added Socrates, “but try to excite
your men to those exertions by which you will both be benefited yourself,
and your countrymen through your means.” “I will assuredly try,” replied
he.
CHAPTER IV
Nicomachides complaining that the Athenians had not chosen him general, though he was experienced in war, but Antisthenes, who had seen no military service, Socrates proceeds to show that Antisthenes, although he had never filled the office of commander, might have qualities to indicate that he would fill it with success.
1. Seeing Nicomachides, one day, coming from the assembly for the election of magistrates, he asked him, “Who have been chosen generals, Nicomachides?” “Are not the Athenians the same as ever, Socrates?” he replied; “for they have not chosen me, who am worn out with serving from the time I was first elected, both as captain and centurion, and with having received so many wounds from the enemy (he then drew aside his robe, and showed the scars of the wounds), but have elected Antisthenes, who has never served in the heavy-armed infantry, nor done anything remarkable in the cavalry, and who indeed knows nothing, but how to get money.” 2. “Is it not good, however, to know this,” said Socrates, “since he will then be able to get necessaries for the troops?” “But merchants,” replied Nicomachides, “are able to collect money; and yet would not, on that account, be capable of leading an army.” 3. “Antisthenes, however,” continued Socrates, “is given to emulation, a quality necessary in a general. Do you not know that whenever he has been chorusmanager he has gained the superiority in all his choruses?” “But, by Jupiter,” rejoined Nicomachides, “there is nothing similar in managing a chorus and an army.” 4. “Yet Antisthenes,” said Socrates, “though neither skilled in music nor in teaching a chorus, was able to find out the best masters in these departments.” “In the army, accordingly,” exclaimed Nicomachides, “he will find others to range his troops for him, and others to fight for him!” 5. “Well, then,” rejoined Socrates, “if he find out and select the best men in military affairs, as he has done in the conduct of his choruses, he will probably attain superiority in this respect also; and it is likely that he will be more willing to spend money for a victory in war on behalf of the whole state, than for a victory with a chorus in behalf of his single tribe.” 6. “Do you say, then, Socrates,” said he, “that it is in the power of the same man to manage a chorus well, and to manage an army well?” “I say,” said Socrates, “that over whatever a man may preside, he will, if he knows what he needs, and is able to provide it, be a good president, whether he have the direction of a chorus, a family, a city, or an army.” 7. “By Jupiter, Socrates,” cried Nicomachides, “I should never have expected to hear from you that good managers of a family would also be good generals.” “Come, then,” proceeded Socrates, “let us consider what are the duties of each of them, that we may understand whether they are the same, or are in any respect different.” “By all means,” said he. 8. “Is it not, then, the duty of both,” asked Socrates, “to render those under their command obedient and submissive to them?” “Unquestionably.” “Is it not also the duty of both to appoint fitting persons to fulfill the various duties?” “That is also unquestionable.” “To punish the bad, and to honor the good, too, belongs, I think, to each of them.” “Undoubtedly.” 9. “And is it not honorable in both to render those under them welldisposed towards them? “ “That also is certain.” “And do you think it for the interest of both to gain for themselves allies and auxiliaries or not?” “It assuredly is for their interest.” “Is it not proper for both also to be careful of their resources?” “Assuredly.” “And is it not proper for both, therefore, to be attentive and industrious in their respective duties?” 10. “All these particulars,” said Nicomachides, “are common alike to both; but it is not common to both to fight.” “Yet both have doubtless enemies,” rejoined Socrates. “That is probably the case,” said the other. “Is it not for the interest of both to gain the superiority over those enemies?” 11. “Certainly; but to say nothing on that point, what, I ask, will skill in managing a household avail, if it be necessary to fight?” “It will doubtless, in that case, be of the greatest avail,” said Socrates; “for a good manager of a house, knowing that nothing is so advantageous or profitable as to get the better of your enemies when you contend with them, nothing so unprofitable and prejudicial as to be defeated, will zealously seek and provide everything that may conduce to victory, will carefully watch and guard against whatever tends to defeat, will vigorously engage if he sees that his force is likely to conquer, and, what is not the least important point, will cautiously avoid engaging if he find himself insufficiently prepared. 12. Do not, therefore, Nicomachides,” he added, “despise men skillful in managing a household; for the conduct of private affairs differs from that of public concerns only in magnitude; in other respects they are similar; but what is most to be observed, is, that neither of them are managed without men, and that private matters are not managed by one species of men, and public matters by another; for those who conduct public business make use of men not at all differing in nature from those whom the managers of private affairs employ; and those who know how to employ them, conduct either private or public affairs judiciously, while those who do not know, will err in the management of both.”
CHAPTER V
Conversation of Socrates with Pericles the younger on the manner in which the Athenians might be made to recover their ancient spirit and ambition. They ought to be reminded of the deeds of their ancestors, sect. 1-12 ; and to be taught that indolence has been the cause of their degeneracy, 13. They ought to revive the institutions of their forefathers, or imitate those of the Lacedaemonians, 14; and to pay great attention to military affairs, 15-25. How the territory of Attica might be best secured against invasion, 26-28.
1. Conversing, on one occasion, with Pericles, the son of the great Pericles,
Socrates said, “I have hopes, Pericles, that under your leadership the
city will become more eminent and famous in military affairs, and will
get the better of her enemies.” “I wish, Socrates,” said Pericles, “that
what you say may happen; but how such effects are to be produced, I cannot
understand.” “Are you willing, then,” asked Socrates, “that we should have
some conversation on these points, and consider how far there is a possibility
of effecting what we desire?” “I am quite willing,” replied Pericles. 2.
“Are you aware, then,” said Socrates, “that the Athenians are not at all
inferior in number to the Boeotians?” “I am,” said Pericles. “And whether
do you think that a greater number of efficient and well-formed men could
be selected from the Boeotians, or from the Athenians?” “The Athenians
do not appear to me to be inferior in this respect.” “And which of the
two peoples do you consider to be best disposed towards each other?” “I
think that the Athenians are; for many of the Boeotians, being oppressed
by the Thebans, entertain hostile feelings towards them. But at Athens
I see nothing of the kind.” 3. “But the Athenians are moreover of all people
most eager for honor and most friendly in disposition; qualities which
most effectually impel men to face danger in the cause of glory and of
their country.” “The Athenians are certainly not to be found fault with
in these respects.” “And assuredly there is no people that have a record
of greater or more numerous exploits of their ancestors than the Athenians;
a circumstance by which many are prompted and stimulated to cultivate manly
courage and to become brave.” 4. “All that you say is true, Socrates, but
you see that since the slaughter of the thousand occurred at Lebadeia under
Tolmides, and that at Delium under Hippocrates, the reputation of the Athenians
has been lessened as far as regards the Boeotians, and the spirit of the
Boeotians has been raised as far as regards the Athenians, so that the
Boeotians, indeed, who formerly did not dare, even on their own soil, to
meet the Athenians in the field without the aid of the Spartans and other
Peloponnesians, now threaten to invade Attica single-handed; while the
Athenians, who formerly, when the Boeotians were unsupported, ravaged Boeotia,
are afraid lest the Boeotians should lay waste Attica.” 5. “I perceive,
indeed,” said Socrates, “that such is the case; but the city seems to me
now to be more favorably disposed for any good general; for confidence
produces in men carelessness, indolence, and disobedience, but fear renders
them more attentive, obedient, and orderly. 6. You may form a notion of
this from people in a ship; for as long as they fear nothing, they are
all in disorder, but as soon as they begin to dread a storm, or the approach
of an enemy, they not only do everything that they are told to do, but
are hushed in silence, waiting for the directions to be given, like a band
of dancers.” 7. “Well then,” said Pericles, “if they would now, assuredly,
obey, it would be time for us to discuss how we might incite them to struggle
to regain their ancient spirit, glory, and happiness.” 8. “If then,” said
Socrates, “we wished them to claim property of which others were in possession,
we should most effectively urge them to lay claim to it, if we proved that
it belonged to their fathers, and was their rightful inheritance; and since
we wish that they should strive for pre-eminence in valor, we must show
them that such pre-eminence was indisputably theirs of old, and that if
they now exert themselves to recover it, they will be the most powerful
of all people.” 9. “How, then, can we convince them of this?” “I think
that we may do so, if we remind them that they have heard that their most
ancient forefathers, of whom we have any knowledge, were the bravest of
men.” 10. “Do you allude to the dispute between the gods, of which Cecrops
and his assessors had the decision on account of their valor?” “I do allude
to that, and to the education and birth of Erechtheus, and the war which
occurred in his time with the people of the whole adjoining continent,
as well as that which was waged under the Heracleidae against the Peloponnesians,
and all the wars that were carried on under Theseus, in all of which they
showed themselves the bravest people of their time; 11. and also, if you
please, to what their descendants have since done, who lived not long before
our day, not only contending, with their own unassisted strength, against
the lords of all Asia and Europe, as far as Macedonia (who inherited vast
power and wealth from their ancestors, and who had themselves performed
great achievements), but also distinguished themselves, in conjunction
with the Peloponnesians, both by land and sea. They, doubtless, are celebrated
as having far surpassed other men of their time.” “They are so,” said Pericles.
12. “In consequence, though many migrations occurred in Greece, they remained
in their own country; and many, when contending for their rights, submitted
their claims to their arbitration, while many others, also, when persecuted
by more powerful people, sought refuge with them.” 13. “I wonder, indeed,
Socrates,” said Pericles, “how our city ever degenerated.” “I imagine,”
said Socrates, “that as some athletes, owing to being prominent and distinguished,
grow idle, and are left behind by their antagonists, so likewise the Athenians,
after attaining great pre-eminence, grew neglectful of themselves, and
consequently became degenerate.”
14. “By what means, then,” said Pericles, “could they now recover their
pristine dignity?” “It appears to me,” replied Socrates, “not at all difficult
to discover; for I think that if they learn what were the practices of
their ancestors, and observe them not less diligently than they, they will
become not at all inferior to them; but if they do not take that course,
yet, if they imitate those who are now at the head of Greece, adopting
the same principles as they do, and practicing the same with diligence
equal to theirs, they will stand not at all below them, and, if they use
greater exertion, even above them.” 15. “You intimate,” returned Pericles,
“that honor and virtue are far away from our city; for when will the Athenians
reverence their elders as the Spartans do, when they begin, even by their
own fathers, to show disrespect to older men? Or when will they exercise
themselves like them, when they not only are regardless of bodily vigor,
but deride those who cultivate it? 16. Or when will they obey the magistrates
like them, when they make it their pride to set them at nought? Or when
will they be of one mind like them, when, instead of acting in concert
for their mutual interests, they inflict injuries on one another, and envy
one another more than they envy the rest of mankind? More than any other
people, too, do they dispute in their private and public meetings; they
institute more law-suits against one another, and prefer thus to prey upon
one another than to unite for their mutual benefit. They conduct their
public affairs as if they were those of a foreign state; they contend about
the management of them, and rejoice, above all things, in having power
to engage in such contests. 17. From such conduct much ignorance and baseness
prevail in the republic, and much envy and mutual hatred are engendered
in the breasts of the citizens; on which accounts I am constantly in the
greatest fear lest some evil should happen to the state too great for it
to bear.” 18. “Do not by any means suppose, Pericles,” rejoined Socrates,
“that the Athenians are thus disordered with an incurable depravity. Do
you not see how orderly they are in their naval proceedings, how precisely
they obey the presidents in the gymnastic games, and how, in the arrangement
of the choruses, they submit to the directions of their teachers in a way
inferior to none?” 19. “This is indeed surprising,” said Pericles, “that
men of that class should obey those who are set over them, and that the
infantry and cavalry, who are thought to excel the ordinary citizens in
worth and valor, should be the least obedient of all the people.” 20. “The
council of the Areopagus, too,” said Socrates, “is it not composed of men
of approved character?” “Undoubtedly,” replied Pericles. “And do you know
of any judges who decide causes, and conduct all their business, with more
exact conformity to the laws, or with more honor and justice? “ “I find
no fault with them,” said Pericles. “We must not therefore despair,” said
Socrates, “as if we thought that the Athenians are not inclined to be lovers
of order.” 21. “Yet in military affairs,” observed Pericles, “in which
it is most requisite to act with prudence, and order, and obedience, they
pay no regard to such duties.” “It may be so,” returned Socrates, “for
perhaps in military affairs men who are greatly deficient in knowledge
have the command of them. Do you not observe that of harpplayers, choristers,
dancers, wrestlers, or pancratiasts, no one ventures to assume the direction
who has not the requisite knowledge for it, but that all, who take the
lead in such matters, are able to show from whom they learned the arts
in which they are masters; whereas the most of our generals undertake to
command without previous study? 22. I do not, however, imagine you to be
one of that sort; for I am sensible that you can tell when you began to
learn generalship not less certainly than when you began to learn wrestling.
I am sure, too, that you have learned, and keep in mind, many of your father’s
principles of warfare, and that you have collected many others from every
quarter whence it was possible to acquire anything that would add to your
skill as a commander. 23. I have no doubt that you take great care that
you may not unawares be ignorant of anything conducive to generalship,
and that, if you have ever found yourself deficient in any such matters,
you have applied to persons experienced in them, sparing neither presents
nor civilities, that you might learn from them what you did not know, and
might render them efficient helpers to you.” 24. “You make me well aware,
Socrates,” said Pericles, “that you do not say this from a belief that
I have diligently attended to these matters, but from a wish to convince
me that he who would be a general must attend to all such studies; and
I indeed agree with you in that opinion.”
25. “Have you considered this also, Pericles,” asked Socrates, “that on the frontier of our territories lie great mountains, extending down to Boeotia, through which there lead into our country narrow and precipitous defiles; and that our country is girded by strong mountains, as it lies in the midst of them?” “Certainly,” said he. 26. “Have you heard, too, that the Mysians and Pisidians, who occupy extremely strong positions in the country of the Great King, and who are lightly armed, are able to make descents on the king’s territory, and do it great damage, while they themselves preserve their liberty?” “This, too, I have heard,” said Pericles. 27. “And do you not think that the Athenians,” said Socrates, “if equipped with light arms while they are of an age for activity, and occupying the mountains that fence our country, might do great mischief to our enemies, and form a strong bulwark for the inhabitants of our country?” “I think, Socrates,” said he, “that all these arrangements would be useful.” 28. “If these plans, then,” concluded Socrates, “appear satisfactory to you, endeavor, my excellent friend, to act upon them; for whatsoever of them you carry into execution, it will be an honor to yourself and an advantage to the state; and if you fail in the attempt for want of power, you will neither injure the state nor disgrace yourself.”
CHAPTER VI
Socrates, by his usual process of interrogation, leads Glaucon, a young
man who was extravagantly desirous of a post in the government, to confess
that he was entirely destitute of the knowledge necessary for the office
to which he aspired. He then shows that, unless a ruler has acquired an
exact knowledge of state affairs, he can do no good to his country or credit
to himself.
1. When Glaucon, the son of Ariston, attempted to harangue the people,
from a desire, though he was not yet twenty years of age, to have a share
in the government of the state, no one of his relatives, or other friends,
could prevent him from getting himself dragged down from the tribunal,
and making himself ridiculous; but Socrates alone, who had a friendly feeling
towards him on account of Charmides the son of Glaucon, as well as on account
of Plato, stopped him. 2. Meeting him by chance, he first stopped him by
addressing him as follows, that he might be willing to listen to him: “Glaucon,”
said he, “have you formed an intention to govern the state for us?” “I
have, Socrates,” replied Glaucon. “By Jupiter,” rejoined Socrates, “it
is an honorable office, if any other among men be so; for it is certain
that, if you attain your object, you will be able yourself to secure whatever
you may desire, and will be in a condition to benefit your friends; you
will raise your father’s house, and increase the power of your country;
you will be celebrated, first of all in your own city, and afterwards throughout
Greece, and perhaps also, like Themistocles, among the Barbarians; and,
wherever you may be, you will be an object of general admiration.” 3. Glaucon,
hearing this, was highly elated, and cheerfully stayed to listen. Socrates
next proceeded to say, “But it is plain, Glaucon, that if you wish to be
honored, you must benefit the state.” “Certainly,” answered Glaucon. “Then,
in the name of the gods,” said Socrates, “do not hide from us, but inform
us with what proceeding you will begin to benefit the state?” 4. But as
Glaucon was silent, as if just considering how he should begin, Socrates
said, “As, if you wished to aggrandize the family of a friend, you would
endeavor to make it richer, tell me whether you will in like manner also
endeavor to make the state richer?” “Assuredly,” said he. 5. “Would it
then be richer, if its revenues were increased?” “That is at least probable,”
said Glaucon. “Tell me then,” proceeded Socrates, “from what the revenues
of the state arise, and what is their amount; for you have doubtless considered,
in order that if any of them fall short, you may make up the deficiency,
and that if any of them fail, you may procure fresh supplies.” “These matters,
by Jupiter,” replied Glaucon, “I have not considered.” 6. “Well then,”
said Socrates, “if you have omitted to consider this point, tell me at
least the annual expenditure of the state; for you undoubtedly mean to
retrench whatever is superfluous in it.” “lndeed,” replied Glaucon, “I
have not yet had time to turn my attention to that subject.” “We will therefore,”
said Socrates, “put off making our state richer for the present; for how
is it possible for him who is ignorant of its expenditure and its income
to manage those matters?” 7. “But, Socrates,” observed Glaucon, “it is
possible to enrich the state at the expense of our enemies.” “Extremely
possible indeed,” replied Socrates, “if we be stronger than they; but if
we be weaker, we may lose all that we have.” “What you say is true,” said
Glaucon. 8. “Accordingly,” said Socrates, “he who deliberates with whom
he shall go to war, ought to know the force both of his own country and
of the enemy, so that, if that of his own country be superior to that of
the enemy, he may advise it to enter upon the war, but, if inferior, may
persuade it to be cautious of doing so.” “You say rightly,” said Glaucon.
9. “In the first place, then,” proceeded Socrates, “tell us the strength
of the country by land and sea, and next that of the enemy.” “But, by Jupiter,”
exclaimed Glaucon, “I should not be able to tell you on the moment, and
at a word.” “Well, then, if you have it written down,” said Socrates, “bring
it, for I should be extremely glad to hear what it is.” “But to say the
truth,” replied Glaucon, “I have not yet written it down.” 10. “We will
therefore put off considering about war before everything else,” said Socrates,
“for it is very likely that, on account of the magnitude of those subjects,
and as you are just commencing your administration, you have not yet examined
into them. But to the defense of the country, I am quite sure that you
have directed your attention, and that you know. how many garrisons are
in advantageous positions, and how many not so, what number of men would
be sufficient to maintain them, and what number would be insufficient,
and that you will advise your countrymen to make the garrisons in advantageous
positions stronger, and to remove the useless ones.” 11. “By Jove,” replied
Glaucon, “(I shall recommend them to remove) them all, as they keep guard
so negligently, that the property is secretly carried off out of the country.”
“Yet if we remove the garrisons,” said Socrates, “do you not think that
liberty will be given to anybody that pleases to pillage? But,” added he,
“have you gone personally, and examined as to this fact, or how do you
know that the garrisons conduct themselves with such negligence?” “I form
my conjectures,” said he. “Well then,” inquired Socrates, “shall we settle
about these matters also, when we no longer rest upon conjecture, but have
obtained certain knowledge?” “Perhaps that,” said Glaucon, “will be the
better course.” 12. “To the silver mines, however,” continued Socrates,
“I know that you have not gone, so as to have the means of telling us why
a smaller revenue is derived from them than came in some time ago.” “I
have not gone thither,” said he. “Indeed the place,” said Socrates, “is
said to be unhealthy, so that, when it is necessary to bring it under consideration,
this will be a sufficient excuse for you.” “You jest with me,” said Glaucon.
13. “I am sure, however,” proceeded Socrates, “that you have not neglected
to consider, but have calculated, how long the corn, which is produced
in the country, will suffice to maintain the city, and how much it requires
for the year, in order that the city may not suffer from scarcity unknown
to you, but that, from your own knowledge, you may be able, by giving your
advice concerning the necessaries of life, to support the city, and preserve
it.” “You propose a vast field for me,” observed Glaucon, “if it will be
necessary for me to attend to such subjects.” 14. “Nevertheless,” proceeded
Socrates, “a man cannot order his house properly, unless he ascertains
all that it requires, and takes care to supply it with everything necessary;
but since the city consists of more than ten thousand houses, and since
it is difficult to provide for so many at once, how is it that you have
not tried to aid one first of all, suppose that of your uncle, for it stands
in need of help? If you be able to assist that one, you may proceed to
assist more; but if you be unable to benefit one, how will you be able
to benefit many? Just as it is plain that, if a man cannot carry the weight
of a talent, he need not attempt to carry a greater weight.” 15. “But I
would improve my uncle’s house,” said Glaucon, “if he would but be persuaded
by me.” “And then,” resumed Socrates, “when you cannot persuade your uncle,
do you expect to make all the Athenians, together with your uncle, yield
to your arguments? 16. Take care, Glaucon, lest, while you are eager to
acquire glory, you meet with the reverse of it. Do you not see how dangerous
it is for a person to speak of, or undertake, what he does not understand?
Contemplate, among other men, such as you know to be characters that plainly
talk of, and attempt to do, what they do not know, and consider whether
they appear to you, by such conduct, to obtain more applause or censure,
whether they seem to be more admired or despised. 17. Contemplate, again,
those who have some understanding of what they say and do, and you will
find, I think, in all transactions, that such as are praised and admired
are of the number of those who have most knowledge, and that those who
incur censure and neglect are among those that have least. 18. If therefore
you desire to gain esteem and reputation in your country, endeavor to succeed
in gaining a knowledge of what you wish to do; for if, when you excel others
in this qualification, you proceed to manage the affairs of the state,
I shall not wonder if you very easily obtain what you desire.”
CHAPTER VII
Socrates exhorts Charmides, a man of ability, and acquainted with public affairs, to take part in the government, that he may not be charged with indolence, sects. 1-4. As Charmides distrusts his abilities for public speaking, Socrates encourages him by various observations, 5-9.
1. Observing that Charmides, the son of Glaucon, a man of worth, and of
far more ability than those who then ruled the state, hesitated to address
the people, or to take part in the government of the city, he said to him,
“Tell me, Charmides, if any man, who was able to win the crown in the public
games, and, by that means, to gain honor for himself, and make his birthplace
more celebrated in Greece, should nevertheless refuse to become a combatant,
what sort of person would you consider him to he?” “I should certainly
think him indolent and wanting in spirit,” replied Charmides. 2. “And if
any one were able,” continued Socrates, “by taking part in public affairs,
to improve the condition of his country, and thus to attain honor for himself,
but should yet shrink from doing so, might not he be justly regarded as
wanting in spirit?” “Perhaps so,” said Charmides; “but why do you ask me
that question?” “Because,” replied Socrates, “I think that you yourself,
though possessed of sufficient ability, yet shrink from engaging even in
those affairs in which it is your duty as a citizen to take a share.” 3.
“But in what transaction have you discovered my ability,” said Charmides,
“that you bring this charge against me?” “In those conferences,” answered
Socrates, “in which you meet those who are engaged in the government of
the state; for when they consult you on any point, I observe that you give
them excellent advice, and that, when they are in any way in the wrong,
you offer judicious objections.” 4. “But it is not the same thing, Socrates,”
said he, “to converse with people in private, and to try one’s powers at
a public assembly.” “Yet,” said Socrates, “he that is able to count, can
count with no less exactness before a multitude than alone, and those who
can play the harp best in solitude are also the best performers on it in
company.” 5. “But do you not see,” said Charmides, “that bashfulness and
timidity are naturally inherent in mankind, and affect us far more before
a multitude than in private conversations?” “But I am prompted to remind
you,” answered Socrates, “that while you neither feel bashfulness before
the most intelligent, nor timidity before the most powerful, it is in the
presence of the most foolish and weak that you are ashamed to speak. 6.
And is it the fullers among them, or the cobblers, or the agricultural
laborers, or the carpenters, or the copper-smiths, or the ship-merchants,
or those who barter in the market, and meditate what they may buy for little
and sell for more, that you are ashamed to address? For it is of all such
characters that the assembly is composed. 7. How then do you think that
your conduct differs from him, who, being superior to well-practiced opponents,
should yet fear the unpracticed? For is not this the case with you, that
though you converse at your ease with those who have attained eminence
in state affairs, and of whom some undervalue you, and though you are far
superior to many who make it their business to address the people, you
yet shrink from uttering your sentiments before men who have never thought
of political affairs, and who have shown no disrespect for your talents,
from an apprehension that you may be laughed at?” 8. “And do not the people
in the assembly,” asked Charmides, “appear to you often to laugh at those
who speak with great judgment?” “Yes,” said Socrates, “and so do the other
sort of people; and therefore I wonder at you, that you so easily silence
one class of persons when they do so, and yet think that you shall not
be able to deal with another. 9. Be not ignorant of yourself, my friend,
and do not commit the error which the majority of men commit; for most
persons, though they are eager to look into the affairs of others, give
no thought to the examination of their own. Do not you, then, neglect this
duty, but strive more and more to attend to yourself; and do not be regardless
of the affairs of your country, if any department of them can be improved
by your means; for, if they are in a good condition, not only the rest
of your countrymen, but your own friends and yourself, will reap the greatest
benefit.”
CHAPTER VIII
Socrates meets the captious questions of Aristippus about goodness and
beauty in such a manner as to show that nothing is good or bad in itself,
but only with reference to some object, sect. 1-3 ; and that nothing is
beautiful or otherwise in itself, but that the beautiful must be considered
with regard to the useful, 4-7. His remarks on buildings, to the same effect,
8-10.
1. When Aristippus attempted to confute Socrates, as he himself had previously
been confuted by him, Socrates, wishing to benefit those who were with
him, gave his answers, not like those who are on their guard lest their
words be perverted, but like those who are persuaded that they ought above
all things to do what is right. 2. What Aristippus had asked him, was,
“whether he knew anything good,” in order that if he should say any such
thing as food, or drink, or money, or health, or strength, or courage,
he might prove that it was sometimes an evil. But Socrates, reflecting
that if anything troubles us, we want something to relieve us from it,
replied, as it seemed best to do, “Do you ask me whether I know anything
good for a fever?” 3. “I do not.” “Anything good for soreness of the eyes?”
“No.” “For hunger?” “No, nor for hunger either.” “Well then,” concluded
Socrates, “if you ask me whether I know anything good that is good for
nothing, I neither know anything, nor wish to know.”
4. Aristippus again asking him if he knew anything beautiful, he replied,
“Many things.” “Are they then,” inquired Aristippus, “all like each other?”
“Some of them,” answered Socrates, “are as unlike one another as it is
possible for them to be.” “How then,” said he, “can what is beautiful be
unlike what is beautiful?” “Because, assuredly,” replied Socrates, “one
man, who is beautifully formed for wrestling, is unlike another who is
beautifully formed for running; and a shield, which is beautifully formed
for defense, is as unlike as possible to a dart, which is beautifully formed
for being forcibly and swiftly hurled.” 5. “You answer me,” said Aristippus,
“in the same manner as when I asked you whether you knew anything good.”
“And do you imagine,” said Socrates, “that the good is one thing, and the
beautiful another? Do you not know that with reference to the same objects
all things are both beautiful and good? Virtue, for instance, is not good
with regard to some things and beautiful with regard to others; and persons,
in the same way, are called beautiful and good with reference to the same
objects; and human bodies, too, with reference to the same objects, appear
beautiful and good; and in like manner all other things, whatever men use,
are considered beautiful and good with reference to the objects for which
they are serviceable.” 6. “Can a dung-basket, then,” said Aristippus, “be
a beautiful thing?” “Yes, by Jupiter,” returned Socrates, “and a golden
shield may be an ugly thing, if the one be beautifully formed for its particular
uses, and the other ill formed.” 7. “Do you say, then, that the same things
may be both beautiful and ugly?” “Yes, undoubtedly, and also that they
may be good and bad; for oftentimes what is good for hunger is bad for
a fever, and what is good for a fever is bad for hunger; oftentimes what
is beautiful in regard to running is the reverse in regard to wrestling,
and what is beautiful in regard to wrestling is the reverse in regard to
running; for whatever is good is also beautiful, in regard to purposes
for which it is well adapted, and whatever is bad is the reverse of beautiful,
in regard to purposes for which it is ill adapted.”
8. When Socrates said, too, that the same houses that were beautiful were
also useful, he appeared to me to instruct us what sort of houses we ought
to build. He reasoned on the subject thus, “Should not he, who purposes
to have a house such as it ought to be, contrive that it may be most pleasant,
and at the same time most useful, to live in? 9. This being admitted,”
he said, “is it not, then, pleasant to have it cool in summer, and warm
in winter?” When his hearers had assented to this, he said, “In houses,
then, that look to the south, does not the sun, in the winter, shine into
the porticoes, while, in the summer, it passes over our heads, and above
the roof, and casts a shade? If it is well, therefore, that houses should
thus be made, ought we not to build the parts towards the south higher,
that the sun in winter may not be shut out, and the parts towards the north
lower, that the cold winds may not fall violently on them? 10. To sum up
the matter briefly, that would be the most pleasant and the most beautiful
residence, in which the owner, at all seasons, would find the most satisfactory
retreat, and deposit what belongs to him with the greatest safety.”
Paintings and colored decorations of the walls deprive us, he thought, of more pleasure than they give.
The most suitable ground for temples and altars, he said, was such as was
most open to view, and least trodden by the public; for that it was pleasant
for people to pray as they looked on them, and pleasant to approach them
in purity.
CHAPTER IX
Various definitions of fortitude, prudence, and temperance, madness, envy, idleness, command, happiness, given by Socrates. Fortitude is not equal in all men; it may be increased by exercise, sect. 1-3. Prudence and temperance not distinct from each other, 4. Justice, as well as other virtues, is wisdom, 5. The opposite to prudence is madness; ignorance distinct from madness, 6, 7. Envy is uneasiness of mind at the contemplation of the happiness of others, 8. Idleness is forbearance from useful occupation, 9. Command is exercised not by those who bear the name, merely, of kings and rulers, but by those who know how to command, 10-13. The best object of human life is to act well; the difference between acting well and acting fortunately, 14, 13.
1. Being asked, again, whether Fortitude was a quality acquired by education, or bestowed by nature, “I think,” said he, “that as one body is by nature stronger for enduring toil than another body, so one mind may be by nature more courageous in meeting dangers than another mind; for I see that men who are brought up under the same laws and institutions differ greatly from each other in courage. 2. I am of opinion, however, that every natural disposition may be improved, as to fortitude, by training and exercise; for it is evident that the Scythians and Thracians would not dare to take bucklers and spears and fight with the Lacedaemonians; and it is certain that the Lacedaemonians would not like to fight the Thracians with small shields and javelins, or the Scythians with bows. 3. In other things, also, I see that men differ equally from one another by nature, and make great improvements by practice; from which it is evident that it concerns all, as well the naturally ingenious as the naturally dull, to learn and study those arts in which they desire to become worthy of commendation.”
4. Prudence and Temperance he did not distinguish; for he deemed that he who knew what was honorable
and good, and how to practice it, and who knew what was dishonorable, and
how to avoid it, was both prudent and temperate. Being also asked whether
he thought that those who knew what they ought to do, but did the contrary,
were prudent and temperate, he replied, “No more than I think the [openly]
imprudent and intemperate to be so; for I consider that all [prudent and
temperate] persons choose from what is possible what they judge for their
interest, and do it; and I therefore deem those who do not act [thus] judiciously
to be neither prudent nor temperate.”
5. He said, too, that justice, and every other virtue, was [a part of]
prudence, for that everything just, and everything done agreeably to virtue,
was honorable and good; that those who could discern those things, would
never prefer anything else to them; that those who could not discern them,
would never be able to do them, but would even go wrong if they attempted
to do them; and that the prudent, accordingly, did what was honorable and
good, but that the imprudent could not do it, but went wrong even if they
attempted to do it; and that since, therefore, all just actions, and all
actions that are honorable and good, are done in agreement with virtue,
it is manifest that justice, and every other virtue, is [comprehended in]
prudence.
6. The opposite to prudence, he said, was Madness; he did not, however, regard ignorance as madness; though for a man to
be ignorant of himself, and to fancy and believe that he knew what he did
not know, he considered to be something closely bordering on madness. The
multitude, he observed, do not say that those are mad who make mistakes
in matters of which most people are ignorant, but call those only mad who
make mistakes in affairs with which most people are acquainted; 7. for
if a man should think himself so tall as to stoop when going through the
gates in the city wall, or so strong as to try to lift up houses, or attempt
anything else that is plainly impossible to all men, they say that he is
mad; but those who make mistakes in small matters are not thought by the
multitude to be mad; but just as they call “strong desire” “love,” so they
call “great disorder of intellect” “madness.”
8. Considering what Envy was, he decided it to be a certain annoyance, not such as arises, however,
at the ill success of friends, nor such as is felt at the good success
of enemies, but those only, he said, were envious who were annoyed at the
good success of their friends. When some expressed surprise, that any one
who had a friendly feeling for another should feel annoyed at his good
fortune, he reminded them that many are so disposed towards others as to
be incapable of neglecting them if they are unfortunate, but would relieve
them in ill fortune, though they are annoyed at their good fortune. This
feeling, he said, could never arise in the breast of a sensible man, but
that the foolish were constantly affected with it.
9. Considering what Idleness was, he said that he found most men did something; for that dice-players and buffoons did something; but he said that all such persons were idle, for it was in their power to go and do something better; he observed that a man was not idle, however, in passing from a better employment to a worse, but that, if he did so, he, as he [previously] had occupation, acted in that respect viciously.
10. Kings and Commanders, he said, were not those who held scepters merely, or those elected by
the multitude, or those who gained authority by lot, or those who attained
it by deceit, but those who knew how to command. 11. For when some one
admitted that it was the part of a commander to enjoin what another should
do, and the part of him who was commanded, to obey, he showed that in a
ship the skillful man is the commander, and that the owner and all the
other people in the ship were obedient to the man of knowledge; that, in
agriculture, those who had farms, in sickness, those who were ill, in bodily
exercises, those who practiced them, and indeed all other people, who had
any business requiring care, personally took the management of it if they
thought that they understood it, but if not, that they were not only ready
to obey men of knowledge who were present, but even sent for such as were
absent, in order that, by yielding to their directions, they might do what
was proper. In spinning, too, he pointed out that women commanded men,
as the one knew how to spin, and the other did not know. 12. But if any
one remarked in reply to these observations, that a tyrant is at liberty
not to obey judicious advisers, he would say, “And how is he at liberty
not to obey, when a penalty hangs over him that does not obey a wise monitor?
for in whatever affair a person does not obey a prudent adviser, he will
doubtless err, and, by erring, will incur a penalty.” 13. If any one also
observed that a tyrant might put to death a wise counsellor, “And do you
think,” he would say, “that he who puts to death the best of his allies
goes unpunished, or that he is exposed only to casual punishment? Whether
do you suppose that a man who acts thus lives in safety, or, rather, by
such conduct brings immediate destruction on himself?”
14. When some one asked him what pursuit he thought best for a man, he
replied, “good conduct.” When he asked him again whether he thought “good
fortune” a pursuit, he answered, “‘Fortune’ and ‘Conduct’ I think entirely
opposed; for, for a person to light on anything that he wants without seeking
it, I consider to be ‘good fortune,’ but to achieve anything successfully
by learning and study, I regard as ‘good conduct;’ and those who make this
the object of their pursuit appear to me to do well.”
15. The best men, and those most beloved by the gods, he observed, were
those who, in agriculture, performed their agricultural duties well, those
who, in medicine, performed their medical duties well, and those who, in
political offices, performed their public duties well; but he who did nothing
well, he said, was neither useful for any purpose, nor acceptable to the
gods.
CHAPTER X
Socrates was desirous to benefit artisans by discoursing with them on the
principles of their several arts. Of painting, sect. 1. Of representing
perfect beauty, 2. Of expressing the affections of the mind, 3-5. Of statuary,
6-8. In what the excellence of a corslet consists, 9-14.
1. Whenever he conversed with any of those who were engaged in arts or trades, and who wrought at them for gain, he proved of service to them. Visiting Parrhasius the painter one day, and entering into conversation with him, he said, “Pray, Parrhasius, is not painting the representation of visible objects! At least you represent substances, imitating them by means of color, hollow and high, dark and light, hard and soft, rough and smooth, fresh and old.” “What you say is true,” said Parrhasius. 2. “And when you would represent beautiful figures, do you, since it is not easy to find one person with every part perfect, select, out of many, the most beautiful parts of each, and thus represent figures beautiful in every part?” “We do so,” said he. 3. “And do you also,” said Socrates, “give imitations of the disposition of the mind, as it may be most persuasive, most agreeable, most friendly, most full of regret, or most amiable? Or is this inimitable?” “How can that be imitated, Socrates,” said he, “which has neither proportion, nor color, nor any of the qualities which you just now mentioned, and is not even a visible object?” 4. “Is it not often observable in a man that he regards others with a friendly or unfriendly look?” “I think so,” said he. “Is this then possible to be copied in the eyes?” “Assuredly.” “And at the good or ill fortune of people’s friends, do those who are affected at it, and those who are not, appear to you to have the same sort of look?” “No, indeed; for they look cheerful at their good, and sad at their evil, fortune.” “Is it possible, then, to imitate these looks?” “Unquestionably.” 5. “Surely, also, nobleness and generosity of disposition, meanness and illiberality, modesty and intelligence, insolence and stupidity, show themselves both in the looks and gestures of men, whether they stand or move.” “What you say is just.” “Can these peculiarities be imitated?” “Certainly.” “Whether, then,” said Socrates, “do you think that people look with more pleasure on paintings in which beautiful, and good, and lovely characters are exhibited, or those in which the deformed, and evil, and detestable are represented?” “There is a very great difference indeed, Socrates,” replied Parrhasius.
6. Going once, too, into the workshop of Cleito, the statuary, and beginning
to converse with him, he said, “I see and understand, Cleito, that you
make figures of various kinds, runners and wrestlers, pugilists and pancratiasts,
but how do you put into your statues that which most attracts the beholders
through the eye, the lifelike appearance?” 7. As Cleito hesitated, and
did not immediately answer, Socrates proceeded to ask, “Do you make your
statues appear more lifelike by assimilating your work to the figures of
the living?” “Certainly,” said he. “Do you not then make your figures appear
more like reality, and more striking, by imitating the parts of the body,
that are drawn up or drawn down, compressed or spread out, stretched or
relaxed, by the gesture?” “Undoubtedly,” said Cleito. “And the representation
of the passions of men engaged in any act, does it not excite a certain
pleasure in the spectators?” “It is natural, at least, that it should be
so,” said he. “Must you not, then, copy the menacing looks of combatants?
And must you not imitate the countenance of conquerors, as they look joyful?”
“Assuredly,” said he. “A statuary, therefore,” concluded Socrates, “must
express the workings of the mind by the form.”
9. Entering the shop of Pistias, a corslet-maker, and Pistias having shown him some well-made corslets, Socrates observed, “By Juno, Pistias, this is an excellent invention, that the corslet should cover those parts of a man’s body that need protection, and yet should not hinder him from using his hands. 10. But tell me, Pistias,” he added, “why do you sell your corslets at a higher price than other makers, though you neither make them stronger nor of more costly materials?” “Because, Socrates,” said he, “I make them better proportioned.” “And do you make this proportion appear in the measure or weight of your corslets, that you set a higher price on them? For I suppose that you do not make them all equal or similar, if you make them to fit (different persons).” “Indeed,” replied he, “I do make them to fit, for there would be no use in a corslet without that quality.” 11. “Are not then,” said Socrates, “the bodies of some men well-proportioned, and those of others ill-proportioned?” “Certainly,” said Pistias. “How, then,” asked Socrates, “do you make a well-proportioned corslet fit an ill-proportioned body?” “As I make it fit,” answered Pistias; “for one that fits is well-proportioned.” 12. “You seem to me,” said Socrates, “to speak of proportion considered not independently, but with respect to the wearer, as if you should say of a shield, or a cloak, that it is well-proportioned to him whom it suits; and such appears to be the case with regard to other things, according to what you say. 13. But, perhaps, there may be some other considerable advantage in making to fit.” “Tell me, Socrates,” said he, “if you know any.” “Those corslets which fit,” answered Socrates, “are less oppressive by their weight, than those which do not fit, though they be both of equal weight; while those which do not fit are, either from hanging wholly on the shoulders, or from pressing heavily on some other part of the body, inconvenient and uneasy; but those which fit, as they have their weight distributed (so as to be borne) partly by the collar-bone and shoulder, partly by the upper part of the arm, and partly by the breast, back, and stomach, appear almost like, not a burden to be borne, but a natural appendage.” 14. “You have hit upon the very quality,” said Pistias, “for which I consider my manufacture deserving of the very highest price; some, however, prefer purchasing ornamented and gilded corslets.” “Yet if on this account,” said Socrates, “they purchase such as do not fit, they appear to me to purchase an ornamented and gilded annoyance. But,” added he, “since the body does not continue always in the same position, but is at one time bent, and at another straight, how can a corslet, which is exactly fitted to it, suit it?” “It cannot by any means,” said Pistias. “You mean, therefore,” said Socrates, “that it is not those which are exactly fitted to the body that suit, but those that do not gall in the wearing.” “I say what is clearly the case, Socrates,” replied he, “and now you exactly comprehend the matter.”
CHAPTER XI
The visit of Socrates to Theodota, and his discourse with her, sect. 1-9.
He tells her that true friends are not acquired without the manifestation
of kind and good feelings, 9-12. He reminds her that in gratifying the
appetites we must guard against satiety, 13, 14. His jests on taking leave
of her, 15-18.
1. There being at one time a beautiful woman in the city, whose name was
Theodota, a woman ready to form a connection with any one that made advances
to her, and somebody in company with Socrates making mention of her, and
saying that the beauty of this woman was beyond description, and that painters
went to her to take her portrait, to whom she showed as much of her person
as she could with propriety, “We ought then to go and see her,” remarked
Socrates, “for it is not possible to comprehend by hearing that which surpasses
description.” “Will you not be quick and follow me, then,” said he who
had mentioned her.
2. Going, accordingly, to the house of Theodota, and finding her standing to a painter, they contemplated her figure; and when the painter had left off, Socrates said, “My friends, whether ought we to feel obliged to Theodota for having shown us her beauty, or she to us for having viewed it with admiration? If the exhibition be rather of advantage to her, ought not she to feel grateful to us, or if the sight has given rather more pleasure to us, ought not we to feel grateful to her?” 3. Somebody saying that he spoke reasonably, he added, “She, then, for the present, gains praise from us, and, when we have spoken of her to others, will gain profit in addition; but as for us, we now desire to embrace what we have seen, and shall go away excited, and long for her after we are away from her; the natural consequence of which is that we shall be her adorers, and that she will be worshipped as our mistress.” “If this be the case, indeed,” said Theodota, “I must feel gratitude to you for coming to see me.”
4. Soon after, Socrates, seeing her most expensively attired, and her mother
with her in a dress and adornment above the common, with several handsome
female attendants, not unbecomingly apparelled, and her house richly furnished
in other respects, said to her, “Tell me, Theodota, have you an estate?”
“Not I, indeed,” replied she. “But perhaps you have a house that brings
you an income?” “Nor a house either,” said she. “Have you then any slaves
that practice handicrafts?” “No, nor any slaves.” “How then,” said Socrates,
“do you procure subsistence?” “If any one becomes my friend,” she replied,
“and is willing to benefit me, he is my means of subsistence.” 5. By Juno,
Theodota,” rejoined Socrates, “and he is an excellent acquisition to you;
and it is much better to have a flock of friends than of sheep, oxen, and
goats. But,” added he, “do you leave it to chance whether a friend, like
a fly, shall wing his way to you, or do you use any contrivance (to attract
them)?” 6. “And how,” said she, “can I find a contrivance for such a purpose?”
“Much more readily,” said he, “than spiders can; for you know how they
try to get subsistence; they weave fine nets, and feed upon whatever falls
into them.” 7. “And do you advise me, too,” said she, “to weave a net?”
“Yes,” said he, “for you ought not to think that you will catch friends,
the most valuable prey that can be taken, without art. Do you not see how
many arts hunters use to catch hares, an animal of but little worth? 8.
As the hares feed in the night, they procure dogs for hunting by night,
with which they chase them; as they conceal themselves in the day, they
provide other dogs, which, perceiving by the smell the way that they have
gone from their feeding-place to their forms, trace them out; and as they
are swift of foot, so as soon to escape from view by running, they procure
also other dogs, of great speed, that they may be caught by pursuit; and
because some of them escape even from these dogs, they stretch nets across
the path by which they flee, that they may fall into them and be entangled.”
9. “By what art of this kind, then,” said she, “can I catch friends?” “If,”
said he, “instead of a dog, you get somebody to track and discover the
lovers of beauty, and the wealthy, and who, when he has found them, will
contrive to drive them into your nets.” “And what nets have I?” said she.
10. “You have one at least,” he replied, “and one that closely embraces
its prey, your person; and in it you have a mind, by which you understand
how you may gratify a person by looking at him, and what you may say to
cheer him, and learn that you ought to receive with transport him who shows
concern for you, and to shut out him who is insolent, to attend carefully
on a friend when he is ill, to rejoice greatly with him when he has succeeded
in anything honorable, and to cherish affection in your whole soul for
the man who sincerely cares for you. To love I am sure that you know, not
only tenderly, but with true kindness of heart; and your friends try to
please you, I know, because you conciliate them, not with words merely,
but by your behavior towards them.” “Indeed,” replied Theodota, “I use
none of these schemes.” 11. “Yet,” said Socrates, “it is of great importance
to deal with a man according to his disposition, and with judgment; for
by force you can neither gain nor keep a friend, but by serving and pleasing
him the animal is easily taken and attached to you.” “What you say is true,”
said she.
12. “It becomes you, therefore,” proceeded Socrates, “in the first place,
to request of your lovers only such favors as they will perform with least
cost to themselves; and you must then make a return by obliging them in
a similar way; for thus they will become most sincerely attached to you,
and will love you longest, and benefit you most. 13. But you will please
them most, if you grant them favors only when they solicit them; for you
see that even the most savory meats, if a person offer them to another
before he has an appetite for them, appear to him distasteful; and in the
satisfied they excite even loathing; but if one offers food to another
after having raised an appetite in him, it seems, though it be of a very
ordinary kind, extremely agreeable.” 14. “How then can I,” said she, “excite
such an appetite in any one of those that visit me?” “If when they are
satiated,” said he, “you, in the first place, neither offer yourself to
them, nor remind them of you, until, coming to an end of their satiety,
they again feel a desire for you; and, when they do feel such desire, remind
them (of your fondness) by the most modest address, and by showing yourself
willing to gratify them, holding back, at the same time, until they are
filled with impatient longing; for it is far better to grant the same favors
at such a time, than before they had an appetite for them.” 15. “Why do
not you, then, Socrates,” said she, “become my helper in securing friends?”
“I will indeed,” said he, “if you can persuade me.” “And how then,” said
she, “can I persuade you?” “You yourself will seek and find means to do
so, if you should at all need me.” “Come often to see me, then,” said she.
16. Then Socrates, joking upon her easy life, said, “But, Theodota, it
is not easy for me to find leisure; for my own numerous occupations, private
and public, allow me no rest; and I have female friends also, who will
not suffer me to leave them day or night, learning from me love-charms
and incantations.” 17. “Do you then know such arts, too, Socrates?” said
Theodota. “Through what other influence do you suppose that Apollodorus
here, and Antisthenes, never leave me? and through what other influence
do you suppose that Cebes and Simmias come to me from Thebes? Be assured,
that such effects were not produced without many love-charms, incantations,
and magic wheels.” 18. “Lend me, then, your magic wheel,” said she, “that
I may set it a-going, first of all, against yourself.” “But, by Jupiter,”
exclaimed Socrates, “I do not wish that I should be drawn to you, but that
you should come to me.” “I will come then,” said she, “only take care to
let me in,” “I will let you in,” replied he, “if another more acceptable
than you be not within.”
CHAPTER XII
Socrates shows the benefit of gymnastic exercises, as well on the health
of the mind as on that of the body, sect. 1-4. The advantages of health
and vigor, 5-8.
1. Noticing that Epigenes, one of his followers, was both very young and
weak in body, he said to him, “How very unlike an athlete you are in frame,
Epigenes!” “I am not an athlete, Socrates,” replied he. “You are not less
of an athlete,” rejoined Socrates, “than those who are going to contend
at the Olympic games. Does the struggle for life with the enemy, which
the Athenians will demand of you when circumstances require, seem to you
to be a trifling contest? 2. Yet, in the dangers of war, not a few, through
weakness of body, either lose their lives, or save them with dishonor;
many, from the same cause, are taken alive, and, as prisoners of war, endure
for the rest of their lives, if such should be their fate, the bitterest
slavery; or, falling into the most grievous hardships, and paying for their
ransom sometimes more than they possess, pass the remainder of their existence
in want of necessaries, and in the endurance of affliction; and many, too,
incur infamy, being thought to be cowards merely from the imbecility of
their bodily frame. 3. Do you think lightly of such penalties attached
to weakness of body, or do you expect that you will endure such calamities
with ease? I believe that what he must bear who attends to the health of
his body, is far lighter and more pleasant than such afflictions. Or do
you suppose that an ill condition of body is more salutary and advantageous
than a good condition? Or do you despise the benefits secured by a good
state of the body? 4. Yet the lot which falls to those who have their bodies
in good condition is exactly the reverse of that which falls to those who
have them in ill condition; for those who have their bodies in a good state
are healthy and strong; and many, from being possessed of this advantage,
save themselves with honor amid the struggles of war, and escape every
peril; many, also, assist their friends and benefit their country, and,
for such services, are thought worthy of favor, acquire great glory, and
attain the highest dignities; and, on these accounts, pass the rest of
their lives with greater pleasure and honor, and bequeath finer fortunes
to their children. 5. Nor, because the city does not require warlike exercises
publicly, ought we, on that account, to neglect them privately, but rather
to practice them the more; for be well assured that neither in any other
contest, nor in any affair whatever, will you at all come off the worse
because your body is better trained (than that of other men); since the
body must bear its part in whatever men do; and in all the services required
from the body, it is of the utmost importance to have it in the best possible
condition; 6. for even in that in which you think that there is least exercise
for the body, namely, thinking, who does not know that many fail greatly
from ill-health? and loss of memory, despondency, irritability, and madness,
often, from ill-health of body, attack the mind with such force as to drive
out all previous knowledge. 7. But to those who have their bodies in good
condition, there is great assurance from danger, and no danger of suffering
any such calamity from weakness of constitution; whilst it is likely, rather,
that a healthy state of body will avail to produce consequences the reverse
of those which result from an unhealthy state of it; and, indeed, to secure
consequences the reverse of what we have stated, what would a man in his
senses not undergo? 8. It is disgraceful, too, for a person to grow old
in self-neglect, before he knows what he would become by rendering himself
well-formed and vigorous in body; but this a man who neglects himself cannot
know; for such advantages are not wont to come spontaneously.”
CHAPTER XIII
Several brief sayings of Socrates. We should not be offended at rudeness
of manner more than at personal defects, sect. 1. Fasting the best remedy
for loathing of food, 2. We should not be too nice as to food or drink,
3. He that punishes his slave, should consider whether he himself deserves
like punishment, 4. Admonitions to travellers, 5. It is disgraceful to
him who has been trained in the gymnasium to be outdone by a slave in enduring
toil, 6.
1. A person being angry, because, on saluting another, he was not saluted
in return, “It is an odd thing,” said Socrates to him, “that if you had
met a man ill-conditioned in body, you would not have been angry, but to
have met a man rudely disposed in mind provokes you.”
2. Another person saying that he ate without pleasure, “Acumenus,” said
Socrates, “prescribes an excellent remedy for that disease.” The other
asking, “What sort of remedy?” “To abstain from eating,” said Socrates;
“for he says that, after abstaining, you will live with more pleasure,
less expense, and better health.”
3. Another saying that the water which he had to drink at his house was
warm, “When you wish to bathe in warm water, then,” said Socrates, “it
will be ready for you.” “But it is (too) cold to bathe in,” said the other.
“Are your slaves, then,” asked Socrates, “inconvenienced by drinking or
bathing in it?” “No, by Jupiter,” replied he; “for I have often wondered
how cheerfully they use it for both those purposes.” “And is the water
in your house,” said Socrates, “or that in the temple of AescuIapius, the
warmer for drinking?” “That at the temple of Aesculapius,” replied he.
“And which is the colder for bathing in, that at your house, or that in
the temple of Amphiaraus?” “That in the temple of Amphiaraus,” said he.
“Consider, then,” said Socrates, “that you run the risk of being harder
to please than your slaves or the sick.”
4. Another person beating his attendant severely, Socrates asked him why
he was so angry at the slave. “Because,” said he, “he is very gluttonous
and very stupid, very covetous and very idle.” “And have you ever reflected,”
rejoined Socrates, “which of the two deserves the greater number of stripes,
you or your slave?”
5. A person being afraid of the journey to Olympia, “Why,” said Socrates
to him, “do you fear the journey? Do you not walk about at home almost
all day? And, if you set out thither, you will walk and dine, walk and
sup, and go to rest. Do you not know that if you were to extend (in a straight
line) the walks which you take in five or six days, you would easily go
from Athens to Olympia? But it will be better for you to start a day too
soon than a day too late; for to be obliged to extend your days’ journeys
beyond a moderate length is disagreeable; but to spend one day more on
the road gives great ease; and it is better, therefore, to hasten to start
than to hurry on the way.”
6. Another saying that he was utterly wearied with a long journey, Socrates
asked him whether he carried any burden. “No, by Jupiter,” said he, “I
did not, except my cloak.” “And did you travel alone,” said Socrates, “or
did an attendant accompany you?” “An attendant was with me.” “Was he empty-handed,
or did he carry anything?” “He carried, certainly, the bedding and other
utensils.” “And how did he get over the journey?” “He appeared to me to
come off better than myself.” “If you, then, had been obliged to carry
his burden, how do you imagine that you would have fared?” “Very ill, by
Jupiter; or rather, I should not have been able to carry it at all.” “And
how can you think that it becomes a man trained to exercise to be so much
less able to bear fatigue than a slave?”
CHAPTER XIV
Table-talk of Socrates in praise of frugality. In contributions to feasts, one guest should not strive to surpass another in the quality or quantity of what he contributes, sect. 1. He may be called 'opsophagos,' flesh-eater, who eats flesh alone, or with very little bread, 2-4. He that eats of many dishes at once acts foolishly in various ways, 5, 6. He may be truly said 'euoxeisthai,' to banquet, who lives on plain and wholesome food, 7.
1. When, among a number of persons who had met together to sup, some brought
little meat, and others a great quantity, Socrates desired the attendant
either to set the smallest dish on the table for common participation,
or to distribute a portion of it to each. They, accordingly, who had brought
a great deal were ashamed not to partake of what was put on table for the
company in general, and not, at the same time, to put their own on table
in return. They therefore offered their own dishes for the participation
of the company; and when they had no greater share than those who brought
but little, they ceased to buy meat at great cost.
2. Observing one of those at table with him taking no bread, but eating
meat by itself, and a discussion having arisen at the same time about names,
for what cause any particular name was given, “Can we tell,” said Socrates,
“for what cause a man should be called 'opsophagos'? For everybody eats flesh with his bread when he has it; but I do not
suppose that people are called 'opsophagoi' on that account.” “I should think not,” said one of the company. 3. “But,”
said Socrates, “if a person should eat meat by itself without bread, not
for the purpose of training, but of gratifying his appetite, whether would
he seem to be an 'opsophagos' or not?” “Scarcely any other would more justly seem so,” said he. “And
he that eats a great deal of meat with very little bread,” said another
of the company, “what should he be called?” “To me,” replied Socrates,
“it appears that he would justly be called 'opsophagos', and when other men pray to the gods for abundance of corn, he may pray
for abundance of flesh.” 4. When Socrates said this, the young man, thinking
that the words were directed at him, did not indeed leave off eating meat,
but took some bread with it. Socrates, observing him do so, said, “Notice
this young man, you that sit near him, whether he takes bread to his meat,
or meat to his bread.”
5. Seeing another of the company taste of several dishes with the same
piece of bread, “Can any cookery be more extravagant,” said he, “or more
adapted to spoil dishes, than that which he practices who eats of several
at the same time, putting all manner of sauces into his mouth at once?
For as he mixes together more ingredients than the cooks, he makes what
he eats more expensive; and as he mixes what they forbear to mix as being
incongruous, he, if they do right, is in the wrong, and renders their art
ineffectual. 6. And how can it be otherwise than ridiculous,” he added,
“for a man to provide himself with cooks of the greatest skill, and then,
though he pretends to no knowledge of their art, to undo what has been
done by them? But another thing happens to him who is accustomed to eat
of several dishes at once; for, if he has not several sorts of meat before
him, he thinks himself stinted, missing what he has been used to. But he
who is accustomed to make one piece of bread, and one piece of meat, go
together, will be able to partake contentedly of one dish when several
are just at hand.”
7. He observed also that 'euoxeisthai,' “to fare well,” was in the language of the Athenians called 'esthiein' “to eat; “ and that the 'eu', “well,” was added to denote that we should eat such food as would disorder
neither mind nor body, and such as would not be difficult to be procured;
so that he applied 'euoxeisthai,' “to fare well,” to those who fared temperately.
BOOK IV
CHAPTER I
Socrates liked the society of young men; how he judged of them; his desire
that they should be well educated, sect. 1, 2. The more powerful the mind
in youth, the more likely it is, if ill trained, to run into vice, 3, 4.
Happiness does not depend on riches, but on knowledge, and on being useful
to our fellow-creatures, and gaining their esteem, 5.
1. So serviceable was Socrates to others, in every kind of transaction,
and by every possible means, that to any one who reflects on his usefulness
(even though he possess but moderate discernment), it is manifest that
nothing was of greater benefit than to associate with Socrates, and to
converse with him, on any occasion, or on any subject whatever; since even
the remembrance of him, when he is no longer with us, benefits in no small
degree those who were accustomed to enjoy his society, and accepted him
(as a Teacher); for he sought to improve his associates not less in his
humorous than in his serious conversation. 2. He would often say that he
loved some particular person; but he was evidently enamored, not of those
formed by nature to be beautiful, but of those naturally inclined to virtue.
He judged of the goodness of people’s abilities from their quickness in
learning the things to which they gave their attention, from their remembrance
of what they learned, and from their desire for all those branches of knowledge
by means of which it is possible to manage a family, state, and the universe
well, and to govern men and their affairs with success; for he thought
that such characters, when instructed, would not only be happy themselves,
and regulate their own families judiciously, but would be able to render
other men, and other communities (besides their own) happy. 3. He did not
however make advances to all in the same manner. Those who thought that
they had good natural abilities, but despised instruction, he endeavored
to convince that minds which show most natural power have most need of
education, pointing out to them that horses of the best breed, which are
high-spirited and obstinate, become, if they are broken in when young,
most useful and valuable, but if they are left unbroken, remain quite unmanageable
and worthless; and that when hounds are of the best blood, able to endure
toil, and eager to attack beasts, those well trained are most serviceable
for the chase, and every way excellent, but, if untrained, are useless,
rabid, and disobedient. 4. In like manner, he showed that men of the best
natural endowments, possessed of the greatest strength of mind, and most
energetic in executing what they undertake, became, if well disciplined
and instructed in what they ought to do, most estimable characters, and
most beneficent to society (as they then performed most numerous and important
services), but that, if uninstructed, and left in ignorance, they proved
utterly worthless and mischievous; for that, not knowing what line of conduct
they ought to pursue, they often entered upon evil courses, and, being
haughty and impetuous, were difficult to be restrained or turned from their
purpose, and thus occasioned very many and great evils.
5. But those who prided themselves on their wealth, and thought that they required no education, but imagined that their riches would suffice to effect whatsoever they desired, and to gain them honor from mankind, he tried to reduce to reason by saying that the man was a fool who thought that he could distinguish the good and the evil in life without instruction; and that he also was a fool, who, though he could not distinguish them, thought that he would procure whatever he wished, and effect whatever was for his interest, by means of his wealth. He also said that the man was void of sense, who, not being qualified to pursue what was for his good, fancied that he would be prosperous in the world, and that everything necessary for his comfort was fully, or at least sufficiently, provided for him; and that he was equally void of sense, who, though he knew nothing, thought that he would seem good for something because of his riches, and, though evidently despicable, would gain esteem (through their influence).
CHAPTER II
No dependence to be placed on natural abilities without education. Socrates
proceeds to show Euthydemus, a self-conceited young man, that in every
art it is proper to have recourse to instructors, sect. 1, 2. He shows
the folly of a man who should pretend to have learned everything of himself,
3-5. The necessity of instruction in the art of government, 6-7. By a long
series of interrogations Socrates reduces Euthydemus to acknowledge his
ignorance and incompetence, 8-23. The value of self-knowledge, 24-30. Further
instructions given to Euthydemus, 30-40.
1. I will now show how Socrates addressed himself to such as thought that
they had attained the highest degree of knowledge, and prided themselves
on their ability. Hearing that Euthydemus, surnamed the Handsome, had collected
many writings of the most celebrated poets and sophists, and imagined that
by that means he was outstripping his contemporaries in accomplishments,
and had great hopes that he would excel them all in talent for speaking
and acting, and finding, by his first inquiries about him, that he had
not yet engaged in public affairs on account of his youth, but that, when
he wished to do any business, he usually sat in a bridle-maker’s shop near
the Forum, he went himself to it, accompanied by some of his hearers; 2.
and as somebody asked, first of all, “whether it was from his intercourse
with some of the wise men, or from his own natural talents, that Themistocles
attained such a pre-eminence above his fellow-citizens, that the republic
looked to him whenever it wanted the service of a man of ability,” Socrates,
wishing to excite the attention of Euthydemus, said that “it was absurd
to believe that men of ability could not master the lowest mechanical arts
without competent instructors, and to imagine that ability to govern a
state, the most important of all arts, might spring up in men by the unassisted
efforts of nature.”
3. On another occasion, when Euthydemus was one of the company, and Socrates
saw him leaving the meeting, from apprehension lest he should seem to admire
him for his wisdom, he observed, “It is evident, my friends, from the studies
that he pursues, that Euthydemus here, when he comes of age, and the government
give liberty of discussion on any point, will not refrain from offering
his counsel; and I imagine that he has already framed an exordium for his
public oration, taking precaution that he may not be thought to have learned
anything from anybody; and it is pretty certain, therefore, that when he
begins to speak, he will make his opening thus: 4. ‘I, O men of Athens,
have never learned anything from any person, nor, though I heard of some
that were skilled in speaking and acting, have I sought to converse with
them; nor have I been anxious that any one of the learned should become
my master; but I have done the exact contrary; for I have constantly avoided
not only learning anything from any one, but even the appearance of learning
anything; nevertheless I will offer you such advice as may occur to me
without premeditation.’ 5. So it might be proper for those to commence
a speech who desired to obtain a medical appointment from the government;
indeed it would be necessary for them to commence their speech in this
way: ‘I, O men of Athens, have never learned the medical art from any one,
nor have been desirous that any physician should be my instructor; for
I have constantly been on my guard, not only against learning anything
of the art from any one, but even against appearing to have learned the
medical art; nevertheless confer on me this medical appointment; for I
will endeavor to learn by making experiments upon you.’” At this mode of
opening a speech all who were present burst out into laughter.
6. As Euthydemus had now evidently begun to attend to what Socrates was
saying, but was cautious of speaking himself, as thinking by his silence
to clothe himself with reputation for modesty, Socrates, wishing to cure
him of that fancy, said, “It is indeed strange, that those who desire to
play on the lyre, or on the flute, or to ride, or to become expert in any
such accomplishment, should endeavor to practice, as constantly as possible,
that in which they desire to excel, and not by themselves merely, but with
the aid of such as are considered eminent in those attainments, attempting
and undergoing everything, so as to do nothing without their sanction,
as supposing that they can by no other means attain reputation; but that
of those who wish to become able to speak and act in affairs of government,
some think that they will be suddenly qualified to achieve their object,
without preparation or study, and by their own unassisted efforts. 7. Yet
these pursuits are manifestly more difficult of attainment than those,
inasmuch as of the very many who attempt them a much smaller number succeed
in them; and it is evident, therefore, that those who pursue the one are
required to submit to longer and more diligent study than those who pursue
the other.”
8. Socrates used at first to make such remarks, while Euthydemus merely listened; but when he observed that he stayed, while he conversed, with more willingness, and hearkened to him with more attention, he at last came to the bridle-maker’s shop unattended. As Euthydemus sat down beside him, he said, “Tell me, Euthydemus, have you really, as I hear, collected many of the writings of men who are said to have been wise?” “I have indeed, Socrates,” replied he, “and I am still collecting, intending to persevere till I get as many as I possibly can.” 9. “By Juno,” rejoined Socrates, “I feel admiration for you, because you have not preferred acquiring treasures of silver and gold rather than of wisdom; for it is plain you consider that silver and gold are unable to make men better, but that the thoughts of wise men enrich their possessors with virtue.” Euthydemus was delighted to hear this commendation, believing that he was thought by Socrates to have sought wisdom in the right course. 10. Socrates, observing that he was gratified with the praise, said, “And in what particular art do you wish to become skillful, that you collect these writings?” As Euthydemus continued silent, considering what reply he should make, Socrates again asked, “Do you wish to become a physician? for there are many writings of physicians.” “Not I, by Jupiter,” replied Euthydemus. “Do you wish to become an architect, then? for a man of knowledge is needed for that art also.” “No, indeed,” answered he. “Do you wish to become a good geometrician, like Theodorus?” “Nor a geometrician either,” said he. “Do you wish then to become an astronomer?” said Socrates. As Euthydemus said “No,” to this, “Do you wish then,” added Socrates, “to become a rhapsodist? for they say that you are in possession of all the poems of Homer.” “No indeed,” said he, “for I know that the rhapsodists, though accurate in the knowledge of poems, are, as men, extremely foolish.” 11. “You are perhaps desirous then,” proceded Socrates, “of attaining that talent by which men become skilled in governing states, in managing households, able to command, and qualified to benefit other men as well as themselves?” “I indeed greatly desire,” said he, “Socrates, to acquire that talent.” “By Jupiter,” returned Socrates, “you aspire to a most honorable accomplishment, and a most exalted art, for it is the art of kings, and is called the royal art. But,” added he, “have you ever considered whether it is possible for a man who is not just to be eminent in that art?” “I have certainly,” replied he; “and it is not possible for a man to be even a good citizen without justice.” 12. “Have you yourself, then, made yourself master of that virtue?” “I think,” said he, “Socrates, that I shall be found not less just than any other man.” “Are there then works of just men, as there are works of artisans?” “There are, doubtless,” replied he. “Then,” said Socrates, “as artisans are able to show their works, would not just men be able also to tell their works?” “And why should not I,” asked Euthydemus, “be able to tell the works of justice; as also indeed those of injustice; for we may see and hear of no small number of them every day?”
13. “Are you willing then,” said Socrates, “that we should make a delta on this side, and an alpha on that, and then that we should put whatever seems to us to be a work of justice under the delta, and whatever seems to be a work of injustice under the alpha?” “If you think that we need those letters,” said Euthydemus, “make them.”
14. Socrates, having made the letters as he proposed, asked, “Does falsehood
then exist among mankind?” “It does assuredly,” replied he. “Under which
head shall we place it?” “Under injustice, certainly.” “Does deceit also
exist?” “Unquestionably.” “Under which head shall we place that?” “Evidently
under injustice.” “Does mischievousness exist?” “Undoubtedly.” “And the
enslaving of men?” “That, too, prevails.” “And shall neither of these things
be placed by us under justice, Euthydemus?” “It would be strange if they
should be,” said he. 15. “But,” said Socrates, “if a man, being chosen
to lead an army, should reduce to slavery an unjust and hostile people,
should we say that he committed injustice?” “No, certainly,” replied he.
“Should we not rather say that he acted justly?” “Indisputably.” “And if,
in the course of the war with them, he should practice deceit?” “That also
would be just,” said he. “And if he should steal and carry off their property,
would he not do what was just?” “CertainIy,” said Euthydemus; “but I thought
at first that you asked these questions only with reference to our friends.”
“Then,” said Socrates, “all that we have placed under the head of injustice,
we must also place under that of justice.” “It seems so,” replied Euthydemus.
16. “Do you agree, then,” continued Socrates, “that, having so placed them,
we should make a new distinction, that it is just to do such things with
regard to enemies, but unjust to do them with regard to friends, and that
towards his friends our general should be as guileless as possible?” “By
all means,” replied Euthydemus. 17. “Well, then,” said Socrates, “if a
general, seeing his army dispirited, should tell them, inventing a falsehood,
that auxiliaries were coming, and should, by that invention, check the
despondency of his troops, under which head should we place such an act
of deceit?” “It appears to me,” said Euthydemus, “that we must place it
under justice.” “And if a father, when his son requires medicine, and refuses
to take it, should deceive him, and give him the medicine as ordinary food,
and, by adopting such deception, should restore him to health, under which
head must we place such an act of deceit?” “It appears to me that we must
put it under the same head.” “And if a person, when his friend was in despondency,
should, through fear that he might kill himself, steal or take away his
sword, or any other weapon, under which head must we place that act?” “That,
assuredly, we must place under justice.” 18. “You say, then,” said Socrates,
“that not even towards our friends must we act on all occasions without
deceit?” “We must not indeed,” said he, “for I retract what I said before,
if I may be permitted to do so.” “It is indeed much better that you should
be permitted,” said Socrates, “than that you should not place actions on
the right side. 19. But of those who deceive their friends in order to
injure them (that we may not leave even this point unconsidered), which
of the two is the more unjust, he who does so intentionally or he who does
so involuntarily?” “Indeed, Socrates,” said Euthydemus, “I no longer put
confidence in the answers which I give; for all that I said before appears
to me now to be quite different from what I then thought; however, let
me venture to say that he who deceives intentionally is more unjust than
he who deceives involuntarily.”
20. “Does it appear to you, then, that there is a way of learning and knowing
what is just, as there is of learning and knowing letters?” “I think there
is.” “And which should you consider the better scholar, him who should
purposely write or read incorrectly, or him who should do so unawares?”
“Him who should do so purposely, for, whenever he pleased, he would be
able to do both correctly.” “He, therefore, that purposely writes incorrectly
may be a good scholar, but he who does so involuntarily is destitute of
scholarship?” “How can it be otherwise?” “And whether does he who lies
and deceives intentionally know what is just, or he who does so unawares?”
“Doubtless he who does so intentionally.” “You therefore say that he who
knows letters is a better scholar than he who does not know?” “Yes.” “And
that he who knows what is just is more just than he who does not know?”
“I seem to say so; but I appear to myself to say this I know not how.”
21. “But what would you think of the man, who, wishing to tell the truth,
should never give the same account of the same thing, but, in speaking
of the same road, should say at one time that it led towards the east,
and at another towards the west, and, in stating the result of the same
calculation, should sometimes assert it to be greater and sometimes less,
what, I say, would you think of such a man?” “It would be quite clear that
he knew nothing of what he thought he knew.”
22. “Do you know any persons called slave-like?” “I do.” “Whether for their
knowledge or their ignorance?” “For their ignorance, certainly.” “Is it
then for their ignorance of working in brass that they receive this appellation?”
“Not at all.” “Is it for their ignorance of the art of building?” “Nor
for that.” “Or for their ignorance of shoe-making?” “Not on any one of
these accounts; for the contrary is the case, as most of those who know
such trades are servile.” “Is this, then, an appellation of those who are
ignorant of what is honorable, and good, and just?” “It appears so to me.”
23. “It therefore becomes us to exert ourselves in every way to avoid being
like slaves.” “But, by the gods, Socrates,” rejoined Euthydemus, “I firmly
believed that I was studying philosophy, by which I should, as I expected,
be made fully acquainted with all that was proper to be known by a man
striving after honor and virtue; but now, how dispirited must you think
I feel, when I see that, with all my previous labor, I am not even able
to answer a question about what I ought most of all to know, and am acquainted
with no other course which I may pursue to become better!”
24. Socrates then said, “Tell me, Euthydemus, have you ever gone to Delphi?” “Yes, twice,” replied he. “And did you observe what is written somewhere on the temple wall, KNOW THYSELF?” “I did.” “And did you take no thought of that inscription, or did you attend to it, and try to examine yourself, to ascertain what sort of character you are?” “I did not indeed try, for I thought that I knew very well already, since I should hardly know anything else if I did not know myself.” 25. “But whether does he seem to you to know himself, who knows his own name merely, or he who (like people buying horses, who do not think that they know the horse that they want to know, until they have ascertained whether he is tractable or unruly, whether he is strong or weak, swift or slow, and how he is as to other points which are serviceable or disadvantageous in the use of a horse, so he), having ascertained with regard to himself how he is adapted for the service of mankind, knows his own abilities?” “It appears to me, I must confess, that he who does not know his own abilities, does not know himself.” 26. “But is it not evident,” said Socrates, “that men enjoy a great number of blessings in consequence of knowing themselves, and incur a great number of evils, through being deceived in themselves? For they who know themselves know what is suitable for them, and distinguish between what they can do and what they cannot; and, by doing what they know how to do, procure for themselves what they need, and are prosperous, and, by abstaining from what they do not know, live blamelessly, and avoid being unfortunate. By this knowledge of themselves, too, they can form an opinion of other men, and, by their experience of the rest of mankind, obtain for themselves what is good, and guard against what is evil. 27. But they who do not know themselves, but are deceived in their own powers, are in similar case with regard to other men, and other human affairs, and neither understand what they require, nor what they are doing, nor the characters of those with whom they connect themselves, but, being in error as to all these particulars, they fail to obtain what is good, and fall into evil. 28. They, on the other hand, who understand what they take in hand, succeed in what they attempt, and become esteemed and honored; those who resemble them in character willingly form connections with them; those who are unsuccessful in their affairs desire to be assisted with their advice, and to prefer them to themselves; they place in them their hopes of good, and love them, on all these accounts, beyond all other men. 29. But those, again, who do not know what they are doing, who make an unhappy choice in life, and are unsuccessful in what they attempt, nor only incur losses and sufferings in their own affairs, but become, in consequence, disreputable and ridiculous, and drag out their lives in contempt and dishonor. Among states, too, you see that such as, from ignorance of their own strength, go to war with others that are more powerful, are, some of them, utterly overthrown, and others reduced from freedom to slavery.”
30. “Be assured, therefore,” replied Euthydemus, “that I feel convinced
we must consider self-knowledge of the highest value; but as to the way
in which we must begin to seek self-knowledge, I look to you for information,
if you will kindly impart it to me.” 31. “Well, then,” said Socrates, “you
doubtless fully understand what sort of things are good, and what sort
are evil.” “Yes, by Jupiter,” replied Euthydemus, “for if I did not understand
such things, I should be in a worse condition than slaves are.” “Come then,”
said Socrates, “tell me what they are.” “That is not difficult,” said he,
“for, in the first place, health I consider to be a good, and sickness
an evil, and, in the next, looking to the causes of each of them, as drink,
food, and employments, I esteem such as conduce to health to be good, and
such as lead to sickness to be evil.” 32. “Consequently,” said Socrates,
“health and sickness themselves, when they are the causes of any good,
will be good, and when they are the causes of any evil, will be evil.”
“But when,” exclaimed Euthydemus, “can health be the cause of evil, and
sickness of good?” “When, for example,” said Socrates, “some portion of
a community, from being in good health, take part in a disgraceful expedition
by land, or a ruinous voyage by sea, or in any other such matters, which
are sufficiently common, and lose their lives, while others, who are left
behind from ill-health, are saved.” “What you say is true,” said Euthydemus,
“but you see that some men share in successful enterprises from being in
health, while others, from being in sickness, are left out of them.” “Then,”
said Socrates, “those things which are sometimes beneficial, and sometimes
injurious are not more good than evil?” “Nothing, by Jupiter, is clear
according to this way of reasoning. 33. But as to wisdom, Socrates, it
is indisputably a good thing; for what business will not one who is wise
conduct better than one who is untaught?” “Have you not heard, then, of
Daedalus,” said Socrates, “how he was made prisoner by Minos on account
of his wisdom, and compelled to serve him as a slave; how he was cut off,
at once, from his country and from liberty, and how, when he endeavored
to escape with his son, he lost the child, and was unable to save himself,
but was carried away among barbarians, and made a second time a slave?”
“Such a story is told, indeed,” said Euthydemus. “Have you not heard, too,
of the sufferings of Palamedes? for everybody says that it was for his
wisdom he was envied and put to death by Ulysses.” “That, too, is said,”
replied Euthydemus. “And how many other men do you think have been carried
off to the king on account of their wisdom, and made slaves there?”
34. “But as to happiness, Socrates,” said Euthydemus, “that at least appears to be an indisputable good.” “Yes, Euthydemus,” replied Socrates, “if we make it consist in things that are themselves indisputably good.” “But what,” said he, “among things constituting happiness can be a doubtful good?” “Nothing,” answered Socrates, “unless we join with it beauty, or strength, or wealth, or glory, or any other such thing.” 35. “But we must assuredly join them with it,” said Euthydemus; “for how can a person be happy without them?” “We shall then join with it, by Jupiter,” said Socrates, “things from which many grievous calamities happen to mankind; for many, on account of their beauty, are ruined by those who are maddened with passion for their youthful attractions; many, through confidence in their strength, have entered upon undertakings too great for it, and involved themselves in no small disasters; many, in consequence of their wealth, have become enervated, been plotted against, and destroyed; and many, from the glory and power that they have acquired in their country, have suffered the greatest calamities.” 36. “Well, then,” said Euthydemus, “if I do not say what is right when I praise happiness, I confess that I do not know what we ought to pray for to the gods.”
“These points, however,” proceeded Socrates, “you have perhaps not sufficiently considered, from too confident a belief that you were already well acquainted with them; but since you intend to be at the head of a democratic government, you doubtless know what a democracy is.” “Assuredly,” said he. 37. “Do you think it possible for a person to know what a democracy is, without knowing what the Demos is?” “No, indeed.” “And what do you conceive the Demos to be?” “I conceive it to be the poorer class of citizens.” “Do you know, then, which are the poor?” “How can I help knowing?” “You know then which are the rich?” “Just as well as I know which are the poor.” “Which sort of persons then do you call poor, and which sort rich?” “Those who have not sufficient means to pay for the necessaries of life, I regard as poor; those who have more than sufficient, I consider rich.” 38. “Have you ever observed, then, that to some who have very small means, those means are not only sufficient, but that they even save from them, while, to many, very large fortunes are not sufficient?” “I have indeed,” said Euthydemus, “(for you very properly put me in mind of it), since I have known some princes, who, from poverty, have been driven to commit injustice like the very poorest people.” 39. “Then,” said Socrates, “if such be the case, we must rank such princes among the Demos, and those that have but little we must rank, if they be good managers, among the rich?” “My own want of knowledge, indeed,” said Euthydemus, “obliges me to admit even this; and I am considering whether it would not be best for me to be silent; for I seem to know absolutely nothing.”
He went away, accordingly, in great dejection, holding himself in contempt,
and thinking that he was in reality no better than a slave.
40. Of those who were thus treated by Socrates, many came to him no more;
and these he regarded as too dull to be improved. But Euthydemus, on the
contrary, conceived that he could by no other means become an estimable
character, than by associating with Socrates as much as possible; and he
in consequence never quitted him, unless some necessary business obliged
him to do so. He also imitated many of his habits.
When Socrates saw that he was thus disposed, he no longer puzzled him with
questions, but explained to him, in the simplest and clearest manner, what
he thought that he ought to know, and what it would be best for him to
study.
CHAPTER III
The necessity of temperance or self-control, and of right notions concerning
the gods, sect. 1, 2. The gods have a providential care for mankind, 3-9.
Other animals are formed by the gods for the use of man, 10. In addition
to the senses common to man with the inferior animals, the gods have given
him reason and speech, 11, 12. Though we do not see the gods, we are convinced
of their existence from their works, 13, 14. We ought therefore to pay
them honor according to our means, 15-18.
1. Socrates was never in haste that his followers should become skillful
in speaking, in action, or in invention, but, previous to such accomplishments,
he thought it proper that a love of self-control should be instilled into
them; for he considered that those who had acquired those qualifications
were, if devoid of self-control, only better fitted to commit injustice
and to do mischief. 2. In the first place, therefore, he endeavored to
impress his associates with right feelings towards the gods. Some, who
were present with him when he conversed with others on this subject, have
given an account of his discourses; but I myself was with him when he held
a conversation with Euthydemus to the following effect.
3. “Tell me,” said he, “Euthydemus, has it ever occurred to you to consider
how carefully the gods have provided for men everything that they require?”
“It has indeed never occurred to me,” replied he. “You know at least,”
proceeded Socrates, “that we stand in need, first of all, of light, with
which the gods supply us.” “Yes, by Jupiter,” answered Euthydemus, “for
if we had no light, we should be, as to the use of our eyes, like the blind.”
“But, as we require rest, they afford us night, the most suitable season
for repose.” “That is assuredly,” said Euthydemus, “a subject for thankfulness.”
4. “Then because the sun, being luminous, shows us the hours of the day,
and everything else, while the night, being dark, prevents us from making
such distinctions in it, have they not caused the stars to shine in the
night, which show us the night-watches, and under the direction of which
we perform many things that we require?” “So it is,” said he. “The moon,
too, makes plain to us not only the divisions of the night, but also of
the month.” “Assuredly,” said he. 5. “But that, since we require food,
they should raise it for us from the earth, and appoint suitable seasons
for the purpose, which prepare for us, in abundance and every variety,
not only things which we need, but also things from which we derive pleasure,
(what do you think of such gifts?)” “They certainly indicate love for man.”
6. “And that they should supply us with water, an element of such value
to us, that it causes to spring up, and unites with the earth and the seasons
in bringing to maturity, everything useful for us, and assists also to
nourish ourselves, and, being mixed with all our food, renders it easier
of digestion, more serviceable, and more pleasant; and that, as we require
water in great quantities, they should supply us with it in such profusion,
(what do you think of such a gift?)” “That also,” said he, “shows thought
for us.” 7. “That they should also give us fire, a protection against cold
and darkness, an auxiliary in every art and in everything that men prepare
for their use, (for, in a word, men produce nothing of any consequence
among the various things necessary to life, without the aid of fire,) (what
do you think of such a gift?)” “That, likewise,” said he, “excels in philanthropy.”
8. [“That they should diffuse the air also around us everywhere in such
abundance, as not only to preserve and support life, but to enable us to
cross the seas by means of it, and to get provisions by sailing hither
and thither among foreign lands, is not this a boon inexpressibly valuable?”
“It is indeed inexpressibly so,” replied he.] “That the sun, too, when
it turns towards us in the winter, should approach to mature some things,
and to dry up others whose season (for ripening) has passed away; and that,
having effected these objects, he should not come nearer to us, but turn
back, as if taking care lest he should hurt us by giving us more heat than
is necessary; and that when again, in his departure, he arrives at the
point at which it becomes evident that, if he were to go beyond it, we
should be frozen by the cold, he should again turn towards us, and approach
us, and revolve in that precise part of the heaven in which he may be of
most advantage to us, what do you think of things so regulated?” “By Jupiter,”
replied Euthydemus, “they appear to be appointed solely for the sake of
man.” 9. “Again, that the sun, because it is certain that we could not
endure such heat or cold if it should come upon us suddenly, should approach
us so gradually, and retire from us so gradually, that we are brought imperceptibly
to the greatest extremes of both, (what do you think of that appointment?)”
“I am reflecting, indeed,” said Euthydemus, “whether the gods can have
any other business than to take care of man; only this thought embarrasses
me, that other animals partake in these benefits.”
10. “But is not this also evident,” said Socrates, “that these animals
are produced and nourished for the sake of man? For what other animal derives
so many benefits from goats, sheep, horses, oxen, asses, and other such
creatures, as man? To me it appears that he gains more advantages from
them than from the fruits of the earth; at least he is fed and enriched
not less from the one than from the other; and a great portion of mankind
do not use the productions of the earth for food, but live by herds of
cattle, supported by their milk, and cheese, and flesh; and all men tame
and train the useful sort of animals, and use them as help for war and
other purposes.” “I agree with what you say on that point,” said Euthydemus,
“for I see some animals much stronger than we, rendered so subservient
to men that they use them for whatever they please.” 11. “But that, since
there are numberless beautiful and useful objects in the world, greatly
differing from one another, the gods should have bestowed on men senses
adapted to each of them, by means of which we enjoy every advantage from
them; that they should have implanted understanding in us, by means of
which we reason about what we perceive by the senses, and, assisted by
the memory, learn how far everything is beneficial, and contrive many plans,
by which we enjoy good and avoid evil; 12. and that they should have given
us the faculty of speech, by means of which by information we impart to
one another, whatever is good, and participate in it, enact laws, and enjoy
constitutional government, what think you of such blessings?” “The gods
certainly appear, Socrates, to exercise the greatest care for man in every
way.” “And that, since we are unable to foresee what is for our advantage
with regard to the future, they should assist us in that respect, communicating
what will happen to those who inquire of them by divination, and instructing
them how their actions may be most for their benefit, (what thoughts does
that produce in you?)” “The gods seem to show you, Socrates,” rejoined
he, “more favor than other men, since they indicate to you, without being
asked, what you ought to do, and what not to do.”
13. “And that I speak the truth, you yourself also well know, if you do
not expect to see the bodily forms of the gods, but will be content, as
you behold their works, to worship and honor them. Reflect, too, that the
gods themselves give us this intimation; for the other deities that give
us blessings, do not bestow any of them by coming manifestly before our
sight; and he that orders and holds together the whole universe, in which
are all things beautiful and good, and who preserves it, for us who enjoy
it, always unimpaired, undisordered, and undecaying, obeying his will swifter
than thought and without irregularity, is himself manifested (only) in
the performance of his mighty works, but is invisible to us while he regulates
them. 14. Consider also that the sun, which appears manifest to all, does
not allow men to contemplate him too curiously, but, if any one tries to
gaze on him steadfastly, deprives him of his sight. The instruments of
the deities you will likewise find imperceptible; for the thunderbolt,
for instance, though it is plain that it is sent from above, and works
its will with everything with which it comes in contact, is yet never seen
either approaching, or striking, or retreating; the winds, too, are themselves
invisible, though their effects are evident to us, and we perceive their
course. The soul of man, moreover, which partakes of the divine nature
if anything else in man does, rules, it is evident, within us, but is itself
unseen. Meditating on these facts, therefore, it behoves you not to despise
the unseen gods, but, estimating their power from what is done by them,
to reverence what is divine.”
15. “I feel clearly persuaded, Socrates,” said Euthydemus, “that I shall
never fail, in the slightest degree, in respect for the divine power, but
I am dejected at the thought that no one among mankind seems to me ever
to requite the favors of the gods without due gratitude.” 16. “But be not
dejected at that reflection, Euthydemus,” said Socrates, “for you know
that the deity at Delphi, whenever any one consults him how he may propitiate
the gods, answers, ACCORDING TO THE LAW OF YOUR COUNTRY; and it is the
law, indeed, everywhere, that every man should propitiate the gods with
offerings according to his ability; and how, therefore, can any man honor
the gods better or more piously, than by acting as they themselves direct?
17. It behoves us, however, not to do less than we are able, for, when
any one acts thus, he plainly shows that he does not honor the gods. But
it becomes him who fails, in no respect, to honor the gods according to
his means, to be of good courage, and to hope for the greatest blessings;
for no one can reasonably hope for greater blessings from others than from
those who are able to benefit him most; nor on any other grounds than by
propitiating them; and how can he propitiate them better than by obeying
them to the utmost of his power?”
18. By uttering such sentiments, and by acting according to them himself,
he rendered those who conversed with him more pious and prudent.
CHAPTER IV
Socrates inculcated a love of justice into his followers. He gave them
an example of adherence to justice in his own life, sect. 1-4. He commences
a conversation with Hippias, a sophist, 4-9. It is better to be just than
merely to talk of justice, 10, 11; it is a part of justice to obey the
laws; what a law is, 12-14; who are the best magistrates in states, 15;
a general observance of the laws maintains concord, 16-18; there are certain
unwritten laws, which it is not possible to transgress without incurring
punishment, 19-24; to observe the divine laws is to be just, 25.
1. Concerning justice, too, he did not conceal what sentiments he entertained,
but made them manifest even by his actions, for he conducted himself, in
his private capacity, justly and beneficently towards all men, and, as
a citizen, he obeyed the magistrates in all that the laws enjoined, both
in the city and on military expeditions, so that he was distinguished above
other men for his observance of order. 2. When he was president in the
public assembly, he would not permit the people to give a vote contrary
to law, but opposed himself, in defense of the laws, to such a storm of
rage on the part of the populace as I think that no other man could have
withstood. 3. When the Thirty Tyrants commanded him to do anything contrary
to the laws, he refused to obey them; for both when they forbade him to
converse with the young, and when they ordered him, and some others of
the citizens, to lead a certain person away to death, he alone did not
obey, because the order was given contrary to the laws. 4. When he was
accused by Meletus, and others were accustomed, before the tribunal, to
speak so as to gain the favor of the judges, and to flatter them, and supplicate
them, in violation of the laws, and many persons, by such practices, had
often been acquitted by the judges, he refused, on his trial, to comply
with any practices opposed to the laws, and though he might easily have
been acquitted by his judges, if he had but in a slight degree adopted
any of those customs, he chose rather to die abiding by the laws than to
save his life by transgressing them.
5. He held conversations to this effect with others on several occasions,
and I know that he once had a dialogue of the following kind, concerning
justice, with Hippias of Elis; for Hippias, on his return to Athens after
an absence of some time, happened to come in the way of Socrates as he
was observing to some people how surprising it was that, if a man wished
to have another taught to be a shoemaker, or a carpenter, or a worker in
brass, or a rider, he was at no loss whither he should send him to effect
his object; [nay, that every place, as some say, was full of persons who
would make a horse or an ox observant of right for any one that desired;]
while as to justice, if any one wished either to learn it himself, or to
have his son or his slave taught it, he did not know whither he should
go to obtain his desire. 6. Hippias, hearing this remark, said, as if jesting
with him, “What! are you still saying the same things, Socrates, that I
heard from you so long ago?” “Yes,” said Socrates, “and what is more wonderful,
I am not only still saying the same things, but am saying them on the same
subjects; but you, perhaps, from being possessed of such variety of knowledge,
never say the same things on the same subjects.” “Certainly,” replied Hippias,
“I do always try to say something new.” 7. “About matters of which you
have certain knowledge, then,” said Socrates, “as, for instance, about
the letters of the alphabet, if any one were to ask you how many and what
letters are in the word ‘Socrates,’ would you try to say sometimes one
thing, and sometimes another; or to people who might ask you about numbers,
as whether twice five are ten, would you not give the same answer at one
time as at another?” “About such matters, Socrates,” replied Hippias, “I,
like you, always say the same thing; but concerning justice I think that
I have certainly something to say now which neither you nor any other person
can refute.” 8. “By Juno,” returned Socrates, “it is a great good that
you say you have discovered, since the judges will now cease from giving
contradictory sentences, the citizens will cease from disputing about what
is just, from going to law, and from quarrelling, and communities will
cease from contending about their rights and going to war; and I know not
how I can part with you till I have learned so important a benefit from
its discoverer.” 9. “You shall not hear it, by Jupiter,” rejoined Hippias,
“until you yourself declare what you think justice to be; for it is enough
that you laugh at others, questioning and confuting everybody, while you
yourself are unwilling to give a reason to anybody, or to declare your
opinion on any subject.” 10. “What then, Hippias,” said Socrates, “have
you not perceived that I never cease declaring my opinion as to what I
conceive to be just?” “And what is this opinion of yours?” said Hippias.
“If I make it known to you, not by words merely, but by actions, do not
deeds seem to you to be a stronger evidence than words?” “Much stronger,
by Jupiter,” said Hippias, “for many who say what is just do what is unjust,
but a man who does what is just cannot be himself unjust.” 11. “Have you
ever then found me bearing false witness, or giving malicious information,
or plunging my friends or the state into quarrels, or doing anything else
that is unjust?” “I have not.” “And do you not think it justice to refrain
from injustice?” “You are plainly now,” said Hippias, “endeavoring to avoid
expressing an opinion as to what you think just; for what you say is, not
what the just do, but what they do not do.” 12. “But I thought,” rejoined
Socrates, “that to be unwilling to do injustice was a sufficient proof
of justice. If this, however, does not satisfy you, consider whether what
I next say will please you better; for I assert that what is in conformity
with the laws is just.” “Do you say, Socrates, that to be conformable to
the laws, and to be just, is the same thing?” “I do indeed.” 13. “(I am
puzzled); for I do not understand what you call conformable to law, or
what you call just.” “Do you know the laws of the state?” said Socrates.
“I do,” said the other. “And what do you consider them to be?” “What the
citizens in concert have enacted as to what we ought to do, and what we
ought to avoid doing.” “Would not he, therefore,” asked Socrates, “be an
observer of the laws, who should conduct himself in the community agreeably
to those enactments, and he be a violator of the laws who transgresses
them?” “Undoubtedly,” said Hippias. “Would not he then do what is just
who obeys the laws, and he do what is unjust who disobeys them?” “Certainly.”
“Is not he then just who does what is just, and he unjust who does what
is unjust?” “How can it be otherwise?” “He therefore that conforms to the
laws is just,” added Socrates, “and he who violates the laws, unjust.”
14. “But,” objected Hippias, “how can any one imagine the laws, or obedience
to them, to be a matter of absolute importance, when the very persons who
make them often reject and alter them?” “(That objection is of no consequence,”
said Socrates), “for states, which have commenced war, often make peace
again.” “Undoubtedly they do,” said Hippias. “What difference will there
be in your conduct, then, think you, if you throw contempt on those who
obey the laws, because the laws may be changed, and if you blame those
who act properly in war, because peace may be made? Do you condemn those
who vigorously support their country in war?” “I do not indeed,” replied
Hippias. 15. “Have you ever heard it said of Lycurgus the Lacedaemonian,
then,” said Socrates, “that he would not have made Sparta at all different
from other states, if he had not established in it, beyond others, a spirit
of obedience to the laws? Do you not know, too, that of magistrates in
states, those are thought the best who are most efficient in producing
obedience to the laws, and that that state, in which the citizens pay most
respect to the laws, is in the best condition in peace, and invincible
in war? 16. The greatest blessing to states, moreover, is concord; and
the senates and principal men in them often exhort the citizens to unanimity;
and everywhere throughout Greece it is a law that the citizens shall take
an oath to observe concord, an oath which they everywhere do take; but
I conceive that this is done, not that the citizens may approve of the
same choruses, or that they may praise the same flute-players, or that
they may prefer the same poets, or that they may take delight in the same
spectacles, but that they may obey the laws; for while the citizens adhere
to these, states will be eminently powerful and happy; but without such
unanimity, no state can be well governed, nor any family well regulated.
17. As an individual citizen, too, how could any person render himself
less liable to penalties from the government, or more likely to have honors
bestowed upon him, than by being obedient to the laws? How else would he
incur fewer defeats in the courts of justice, or how more certainly obtain
sentence in his favor? To whom would any one believe that he could more
safely confide his money, or his sons or daughters? Whom would the whole
community deem more trustworthy than him who respects the laws? From whom
would parents, or relatives, or domestics, or friends, or citizens, or
strangers, more certainly obtain their rights? To whom would the enemy
sooner trust in cessation of arms, or in making a truce, or articles of
peace? To whom would people more willingly become allies than to the observer
of the laws, and to whom would the allies more willingly trust the leadership,
or command of a fortress, or of a city? From whom would any one expect
to meet with gratitude, on doing him a kindness, sooner than from the observer
of the laws? Or whom would any one rather serve than him from whom he expects
to receive a return? To whom would any one more desire to be a friend,
or less desire to be an enemy, than such a man? With whom would any one
be less inclined to go to war, than with him to whom he would most wish
to be a friend, and least of all an enemy, and to whom the greatest part
of mankind would wish to be friends and allies, and but a small number
to be antagonists and enemies? 18. I, therefore, Hippias, pronounce that
to obey the laws and to be just is the same; if you hold an opinion to
the contrary, tell me.” “Indeed, Socrates,” rejoined Hippias, “I do not
know that I entertain any sentiments opposed to what you have said of justice.”
19. “But are you aware, Hippias,” continued Socrates, “that there are unwritten
laws?” “You mean those,” said Hippias, “that are in force about the same
points everywhere.” “Can you affirm, then, that men made those laws?” “How
could they,” said Hippias, “when they could not all meet together, and
do not all speak the same language?” “Whom then do you suppose to have
made these laws?” “I believe,” said he, “that it was the gods who made
these laws for men, for among all men the first law is to venerate the
gods.” 20. “Is it not also a law everywhere to honor parents?” “It is so.”
“Is it not a law, too, that parents shall not intermarry with their children,
nor children with their parents?” “This does not as yet, Socrates, appear
to me to be a law of the gods?” “Why?” “Because I find that some nations
transgress it.” 21. “Many others, too, they transgress,” said Socrates;
“but those who violate the laws made by the gods incur punishment which
it is by no means possible for man to escape, as many transgressors of
the laws made by men escape punishment, some by concealment, others by
open violence.” 22. “And what sort of punishment, Socrates,” said he, “cannot
parents escape who intermarry with their children, and children who intermarry
with their parents?” “The greatest of all punishments, by Jupiter,” replied
Socrates, “for what greater penalty can those who beget children incur,
than to have bad children?” 23. “How then,” said Hippias, “do they necessarily
have bad children, when nothing hinders but that they may be good themselves,
and have children by good partners?” “Because,” returned Socrates, “it
is not only necessary that those who have children by each other should
be good, but that they should be in full bodily vigor. Or do you suppose
that the seed of those who are at the height of maturity is similar to
that of those who have not yet reached maturity, or to that of those who
are far past it?” “By Jupiter,” replied Hippias, “it is not at all likely
that it should be similar.” “Which of the two then is the better?” “Doubtless
that of those at full maturity.” “That of those who are not at full maturity,
then, is not sufficiently energetic.” “Probably not.” “Accordingly they
ought not to have children?” “No.” “Do not those, therefore, who have children
under such circumstances, have them as they ought not?” “So it appears
to me.” “What other persons, therefore, will have bad children, if not
these?” “Well,” said Hippias, “I agree with you on this point also.”
24. “Is it not everywhere a law, also,” said Socrates, “that men should
do good to those who do good to them?” “It is a law,” answered Hippias,
“but it is transgressed.” “Those therefore who transgress it incur punishment,”
continued Socrates, “by being deprived of good friends, and being compelled
to have recourse to those who hate them. Are not such as do service to
those who seek it of them good friends, and are not those who make no return
to such as serve them hated by them for their ingratitude; and yet, because
it is for their advantage to have their support, do they not pay the greatest
court to them?” “Indeed, Socrates,” replied Hippias, “all these things
seem to suit the character of the gods; for that the laws themselves should
carry with them punishments for those who transgress them, appears to me
to be the appointment of a lawgiver superior to man.”
25. “Whether, therefore, Hippias,” added Socrates, “do you consider that
the gods appoint as laws, what is agreeable to justice, or what is at variance
with justice?” “Not what is at variance with justice, certainly,” said
Hippias, “for scarcely would any other make laws in conformity with justice,
if a god were not to do so.” “It is the pleasure of the gods, therefore,
Hippias,” concluded Socrates, “that what is in conformity with justice
should also be in conformity with the laws.”
By uttering such sentiments, and acting in agreement with them, he rendered
those who conversed with him more observant of justice.
CHAPTER V
Socrates rendered his followers better qualified for public life. The necessity
of temperance, sect. 1, 2; the evils of intemperance, 3-7; the benefits
arising from temperance, 8-10; the conduct of the temperate man, 11, 12.
1. I will now relate how he rendered his followers better qualified for
the management of public business. Thinking it expedient that temperance
should be observed by him who would succeed in anything honorable, he first
made it evident to those who conversed with him, that he practiced this
virtue beyond all other men, and then, by his discourse, he exhorted his
followers, above everything, to the observance of temperance. He continued
always, therefore, both himself to be mindful of, and to remind all his
followers of, whatever was conducive to virtue; and I know that he once
held a conversation on temperance with Euthydemus to the following effect:
2. “Tell me,” said he, “Euthydemus, do you regard liberty as an excellent
and honorable possession for an individual or a community?” “The most excellent
and honorable that can be,” replied he. 3. “Do you consider him, then,
who is held under control by the pleasures of the body, and is rendered
unable, by their influence, to do what is best for him, to be free?” “By
no means,” replied Euthydemus. “Perhaps, then, to do what is best seems
to you to be freedom, but to be under influences which will hinder you
from doing it, you consider to be want of freedom?” “Assuredly,” said he.
4. “Do not the intemperate appear to you, then, to be absolutely without
freedom?” “Yes, by Jupiter, and naturally so.” “And whether do the intemperate
appear to you to be merely prevented from doing what is best, or to be
forced, also, to do what is most dishonorable?” “They appear to me,” replied
Euthydemus, “to be not less forced to do the one than they are hindered
from doing the other.” 5. “And what sort of masters do you consider those
to be, who hinder men from doing what is best, and force them to do what
is worst?” “The very worst possible, by Jupiter,” replied he. “And what
sort of slavery do you consider to be the worst?” “That,” said he, “under
the worst masters.” “Do not then the intemperate,” said Socrates, “endure
the very worst of slavery?” “It appears so to me,” answered Euthydemus.
6. “And does not intemperance seem to you, by banishing from men prudence,
the greatest good, to drive them into the very opposite evil? Does it not
appear to you to hinder them from attending to useful things, and learning
them, by drawing them away to pleasure, and frequently, by captivating
those who have a perception of good and evil, to make them choose the worse
instead of the better?” “Such is the case,” said he. 7. “And whom can we
suppose, Euthydemus, to have less participation in self-control than the
intemperate man? for assuredly the acts of self-control and of intemperance
are the very opposite to each other.” “I assent to this also,” said he.
“And do you think that anything is a greater hindrance to attention to
what is becoming, than intemperance?” “I do not.” “And do you imagine that
there is any greater evil to man, than that which makes him prefer the
noxious to the beneficial, which prompts him to pursue the one and to neglect
the other, and which forces him to pursue a contrary course of conduct
to that of the wise?” “There is none,” said Euthydemus.
8. “Is it not natural, then,” said Socrates, “that temperance should be
the cause of producing in men effects contrary to those which intemperance
produces?” “Undoubtedly,” said Euthydemus. “Is it not natural, therefore,
also, that what produces those contrary effects should be best for man?”
“It is natural,” said he. “Is it not consequently natural, then, Euthydemus,
that temperance should be best for man?” “It is so, Socrates,” said he.
9. “And have you ever reflected upon this, Euthydemus?” “What?” “That even
to those pleasures, to which alone intemperance seems to lead men, it cannot
lead them, but that temperance produces greater pleasure than anything
else?” “How?” said he. “Because intemperance, by not allowing men to withstand
hunger, thirst, or the desire of sensual gratification, or want of sleep
(through which privations alone is it possible for them to eat, and drink,
and gratify other natural appetites, and go to rest and sleep with pleasure,
waiting and restraining themselves until the inclinations may be most happily
indulged), hinders them from having any due enjoyment in acts most necessary
and most habitual; but temperance, which alone enables men to endure the
privations which I have mentioned, alone enables them to find any delight
worthy of mention in the gratifications to which I have alluded.” “What
you say,” observed Euthydemus, “is indisputably true.” 10. “To learn what
is honorable and good, moreover, and to study those accomplishments by
which a man may ably govern himself, judiciously regulate his household,
become useful to his friends and the state, and gain the mastery over his
enemies (from which studies arise not only the greatest advantages, but
also the greatest pleasures), and of which the temperate have enjoyment
while they practice them, but the intemperate have no share in any of them,
to whom can we say that it less belongs to attend to such things, than
to him who has the least power to pursue them, being wholly occupied in
attention to present pleasures?” 11. “You seem to me, Socrates,” said Euthydemus,
“to say that the man who is under the influence of bodily pleasures, has
no participation in any one virtue.” “For what difference is there, Euthydemus,”
said he, “between an intemperate man and the most ignorant brute? How will
he, who has no regard to what is best, but seeks only to enjoy what is
most seductive by any means in his power, differ from the most senseless
cattle? To the temperate alone it belongs to consider what is best in human
pursuits, to distinguish those pursuits, according to experience and reason,
into their several classes, and then to choose the good and refrain from
the evil.”
12. Thus it was, he said, that men became most virtuous and happy, and most skillful in reasoning; and he observed that the expression 'dialegesthai,' “to reason,” had its origin in people’s practice of meeting together to reason on matters, and distinguishing them, 'dialegontas,' according to their several kinds. It was the duty of every one, therefore, he thought, to make himself ready in this art, and to study it with the greatest diligence; for that men, by the aid of it, became most accomplished, most able to guide others, and most acute in discussion.
CHAPTER VI
The value of skill in argument and definition, sect. 1. Definition of PIETY,
2-4; of JUSTICE, 5, 6; of WISDOM, 7; of GOODNESS and BEAUTY, 8, 9; of COURAGE,
10, 11. Some other definitions, 12. Remarks on the Socratic method of argument,
13-15.
1. I will now endeavor to show that Socrates rendered those who associated
with him more skillful in argument. For he thought that those who knew
the nature of things severally, would be able to explain them to others;
but as to those who did not know, he said that it was not surprising that
they fell into error themselves, and led others into it. He therefore never
ceased to reason with his associates about the nature of things. To go
through all the terms that he defined, and to show how he defined them,
would be a long task; but I will give as many instances as I think will
suffice to show the nature of his reasoning.
2. In the first place, then, he reasoned of PIETY, in some such way as
this. “Tell me,” said he, “Euthydemus, what sort of feeling do you consider
piety to be?” “The most noble of all feelings,” replied he. “Can you tell
me, then, who is a pious man?” “The man, I think, who honors the gods.”
“Is it allowable to pay honor to the gods in any way that one pleases?”
“No; there are certain laws in conformity with which we must pay our honors
to them.” 3. “He, then, who knows these laws, will know how he must honor
the gods?” “I think so.” “He therefore who knows how to pay honor to the
gods, will not think that he ought to pay it otherwise than as he knows?”
“Doubtless not.” “But does any one pay honors to the gods otherwise than
as he thinks that he ought to pay them?” “I think not.” 4. “He therefore
who knows what is agreeable to the laws with regard to the gods, will honor
the gods in agreement with the laws?” “Certainly.” “Does not he, then,
who honors the gods agreeably to the laws honor them as he ought?” “How
can he do otherwise?” “And he who honors them as he ought, is pious?” “Certainly.”
“He therefore who knows what is agreeable to the laws with regard to the
gods, may be justly defined by us as a pious man?” “So it appears to me,”
said Euthydemus.
5. “But is it allowable for a person to conduct himself towards other men
in whatever way he pleases?” “No; but with respect to men also, he who
knows what is in conformity with the laws, and how men ought, according
to them, to conduct themselves towards each other, will be an observer
of the laws.” “Do not those, then, who conduct themselves towards each
other according to what is in conformity with the laws, conduct themselves
towards each other as they ought?” “How can it be otherwise?” “Do not those,
therefore, who conduct themselves towards each other as they ought, conduct
themselves well?” “Certainly.” “Do not those, then, that conduct themselves
well towards each other, act properly in transactions between man and man?”
“Surely.” “Do not those, then, who obey the laws, do what is just?” “Undoubtedly.”
6. “And do you know what sort of actions are called just?” “Those which
the laws sanction.” “Those, therefore, who do what the laws sanction, do
what is just, and what they ought?” “How can it be otherwise?” “Do you
think that any persons yield obedience to the laws who do not know what
the laws sanction?” “I do not.” “And do you think that any who know what
they ought to do, think that they ought not to do it?” “I do not think
so.” “And do you know any persons that do other things than those which
they think they ought to do?” “I do not.” “Those, therefore, who know what
is agreeable to the laws in regard to men, do what is just?” “Certainly.”
“And are not those who do what is just, just men?” “Who else can be so?”
“Shall we not define rightly, therefore,” concluded Socrates, “if we define
those to be just who know what is agreeable to the laws in regard to men?”
“It appears so to me,” said Euthydemus.
7. “And what shall we say that WISDOM is? Tell me, whether do men seem
to you to be wise, in things which they know, or are there some who are
wise in things which they do not know?” “In what they know, certainly;
for how can a man be wise in things of which he knows nothing?” “Those,
then, who are wise, are wise by their knowledge?” “By what else can a man
be wise, if not by his knowledge?” “Do you think wisdom, then, to be anything
else than that by which men are wise?” “I do not.” “Is knowledge, then,
wisdom?” “It appears so to me.” “Does it appear to you, however, that it
is possible for a man to know all things that are?” “No, by Jupiter; not
even, as I think, a comparatively small portion of them.” “It is not therefore
possible for a man to be wise in all things?” “No, indeed.” “Every man
is wise, therefore, in that only of which he has a knowledge?” “So it seems
to me.”
8. “Shall we thus, too, Euthydemus,” said he, “inquire what is GOOD?” “How?”
said Euthydemus. “Does the same thing appear to you to be beneficial to
everybody?” “No.” “And does not that which is beneficial to one person
appear to you to be sometimes hurtful to another?” “Assuredly.” “Would
you say, then, that anything is good that is not beneficial?” “I would
not.” “What is beneficial, therefore, is good, to whomsoever it is beneficial?”
“It appears so to me,” said Euthydemus.
9. “And can we define the BEAUTIFUL in any other way than if you term whatever
is beautiful, whether a person, or a vase, or anything else whatsoever,
beautiful for whatever purpose you know that it is beautiful?” “No, indeed,”
said Euthydemus. “For whatever purpose, then, anything may be useful, for
that purpose it is beautiful to use it?” “Certainly.” “And is anything
beautiful for any other purpose than that for which it is beautiful to
use it?” “For no other purpose,” replied he. “What is useful is beautiful,
therefore, for that purpose for which it is useful?” “So I think,” said
he.
10. “As to COURAGE, Euthydemus,” said Socrates, “do you think it is to be numbered among excellent things?” “I think it one of the most excellent,” replied Euthydemus. “But you do not think courage a thing of use for small occasions?” “No, by Jupiter, but for the very greatest.” “Does it appear to you to be useful, with regard to formidable and dangerous things, to be ignorant of their character?” “By no means.” “They, therefore, who do not fear such things, because they do not know what they are, are not courageous?” “Certainly not; for, in that case, many madmen and even cowards would be courageous.” “And what do you say of those who fear things that are not formidable?” “Still less, by Jupiter, should they be called courageous.” “Those, then, that are good, with reference to formidable and dangerous things, you consider to be courageous, and those that are bad, cowardly?” “Certainly.” 11. “But do you think that any other persons are good, with reference to terrible and dangerous circumstances, except those who are able to conduct themselves well under them?” “No, those only,” said he. “And you think those bad with regard to them, who are of such a character as to conduct themselves badly under them?” “Whom else can I think so?” “Do not each, then, conduct themselves under them as they think they ought?” “How can it be otherwise?” “Do those, therefore, who cannot conduct themselves properly under them, know how they ought to conduct themselves under them?” “Doubtless not.” “Those then who know how they ought to conduct themselves under them, can do so?” “And they alone.” “Do those, therefore, who do not fail under such circumstances, conduct themselves badly under them?” “I think not.” “Those, then, who do conduct themselves badly under them, do fail?” “It seems so.” “Those, therefore, who know how to conduct themselves well in terrible and dangerous circumstances are courageous, and those who fail to do so are cowards?” “They at least appear so to me,” said Euthydemus.
12. Monarchy and tyranny he considered to be both forms of government,
but conceived that they differed (greatly) from one another; for a government
over men with their own consent, and in conformity with the laws of free
states, he regarded as a monarchy; but a government over men against their
will, and not according to the law of free states, but just as the ruler
pleased, a tyranny; and wherever magistrates were appointed from among
those who complied with the injunctions of the laws, he considered the
government to be an aristocracy; wherever they were appointed according
to their wealth, a plutocracy; and wherever they were appointed from among
the whole people, a democracy.
13. Whenever any person contradicted him on any point, who had nothing definite to say, and who perhaps asserted, without proof, that some person, whom he mentioned, was wiser, or better skilled in political affairs, or possessed of greater courage, or worthier in some such respect [than some other whom Socrates had mentioned], he would recall the whole argument, in some such way as the following, to the primary proposition: 14. “Do you say that he whom you commend, is a better citizen than he whom I commend?” “I do say so.” “Why did we not then consider, in the first place, what is the duty of a good citizen?” “Let us do so.” “Would not he then be superior in the management of the public money who should make the state richer?” “Undoubtedly.” “And he in war who should make it victorious over its enemies?” “Assuredly.” “And in an embassy he who should make friends of foes?” “Doubtless.” “And he in addressing the people who should check dissension and inspire them with unanimity?” “I think so.” When the discussion was thus brought back to fundamental principles, the truth was made evident to those who had opposed him.
15. When he himself went through any subject in argument, he proceeded upon propositions of which the truth was generally acknowledged, thinking that a sure foundation was thus formed for his reasoning. Accordingly, whenever he spoke, he, of all men that I have known, most readily prevailed on his hearers to assent to his arguments; and he used to say that Homer had attributed to Ulysses the character of a sure orator, as being able to form his reasoning on points acknowledged by all mankind.
CHAPTER VII
How Socrates rendered his followers 'mechanikous,' ingenious and adapted for business; his frankness and sincerity, 1.
How far he thought that Geometry should be studied, 2, 3. How far he recommended
that Astronomy should be pursued, 4-7. Vain investigations to be avoided,
8. Regard to be paid to health, 9. Counsel to be asked of the gods, 10.
1. That Socrates expressed his sentiments with sincerity to those who conversed
with him, is, I think, manifest from what I have said. I will now proceed
to show how much it was his care that his followers should be competently
qualified for employments suited to their powers. Of all men that I have
known, he was the most anxious to discover in what occupation each of those
who attended him was likely to prove skillful; and of all that it becomes
a man of honor and virtue to know, he taught them himself, whatever he
knew, with the utmost cheerfulness; and what he had not sufficient knowledge
to teach, he took them to those who knew, to learn.
2. He taught them also how far it was proper that a well-educated man should
be versed in any department of knowledge. Geometry, for instance, he said
that a man should study until he should be capable, if occasion required,
to take or give land correctly by measurement; or to divide it or portion
it out for cultivation; and this, he observed, it was so easy to learn,
that he who gave any attention at all to mensuration, might find how large
the whole earth was, and perfectly understand how it was measured. 3. But
of pursuing the study of geometry to diagrams hard to understand, he disapproved;
for he said that he could not see of what profit they were, though he himself
was by no means unskilled in them; but he remarked that they were enough
to consume a man’s whole life, and hinder him from attaining many other
valuable branches of knowledge.
4. He recommended his followers to learn astronomy also, but only so far
as to be able to know the hour of the night, the month, and the season
of the year, with a view to travelling by land or sea, or distinguishing
the earth, the periods of their revolutions, and the divisions of the above
mentioned times, to profit by the signs for whatever other things are done
at a certain period of the night, or month, or year. These particulars,
he said, were easily learned from men who hunted by night, from pilots,
and from many others whose business it was to know them. 5. But to continue
the study of astronomy so far as to distinguish the bodies which do not
move in the same circle with the heaven, the planets, and the irregular
stars, and to weary ourselves in inquiring into their distances from the
earth, the periods of their revolutions, and the causes of all these things,
was what he greatly discountenanced; for he saw, he said, no profit in
these studies either, though he had himself given attention to them; since
they also, he remarked, were enough to wear out the life of a man, and
prevent him from attending to many profitable pursuits.
6. Concerning celestial matters in general, he dissuaded every man from
becoming a speculator how the divine power contrives to manage them; for
he did not think that such points were discoverable by man, nor did he
believe that those pleased the gods who inquired into things which they
did not wish to make known. He observed, too, that a man who was anxious
about such investigations, was in danger of losing his senses, not less
than Anaxagoras, who prided himself highly on explaining the plans of the
gods, lost his. 7. For Anaxagoras, when he said that fire and the sun were
of the same nature, did not reflect that people can easily look upon fire,
but cannot turn their gaze on the sun, and that men, if exposed to the
rays of the sun, have complexions of a darker shade, but not if exposed
to fire; he omitted to consider, too, that of the productions of the earth,
none can come fairly to maturity without the rays of the sun, while, if
warmed by the heat of the fire, they all perish; and when he said that
the sun was a heated stone, he forgot that a stone placed in the fire does
not shine, or last long, but that the sun continues perpetually the most
luminous of all bodies.
8. He advised his followers also to learn computations, but in these, as
in other things, he exhorted them to avoid useless labor; as far as it
was of any profit, he investigated everything himself, and went through
it with his associates.
9. He earnestly recommended those who conversed with him to take care of their health, both by learning whatever they could respecting it from men of experience, and by attending to it, each for himself, throughout his whole life, studying what food or drink, or what exercise, was most suitable for him, and how he might act in regard to them so as to enjoy the best health; for he said it would be difficult for a person who thus attended to himself to find a physician that would tell better than himself what was conducive to his health.
10. But if any one desired to attain to what was beyond human wisdom, he advised him to study divination; for he said that he who knew by what signs the gods give indications to men respecting human affairs, would never fail of obtaining counsel from the gods.
CHAPTER VIII
Socrates, though condemned to death, was not convicted of falsehood with
regard to his DAEMON. His resolution to die. His innocence inspires him
with courage. He thinks it good to die, and escape the evils of old age.
Summary of the arguments of the Memorabilia.
1. But if any one thinks that he was convicted of falsehood with regard
to his DAEMON, because sentence of death was pronounced on him by the judges
although he said that the daemon admonished him what he ought and what
he ought not to do, let him consider, in the first place, that he was already
so advanced in years that he must have ended his life, if not then, at
least not long after; and, in the next, that he relinquished only the most
burdensome part of life, in which all feel their powers of intellect diminished,
while, instead of enduring this, he acquired great glory by proving the
firmness of his mind, pleading his cause, above all men, with the greatest
regard to truth, ingenuousness, and justice, and bearing his sentence at
once with the utmost resignation and the utmost fortitude.
2. It is indeed acknowledged that no man, of all that are remembered, ever endured death with greater glory; for he was obliged to live thirty days after his sentence, because the Delian festival happened in that month, and the law allowed no one to be publicly put to death until the sacred deputation should return from Delos; and during that time he was seen by all his friends living in no other way than at any preceding period; and, let it be observed, throughout all the former part of his life he had been admired beyond all men for the cheerfulness and tranquillity with which he lived. 3. How could any one have died more nobly than thus? Or what death could be more honorable than that which any man might most honorably undergo? Or what death could be happier than the most honorable? Or what death more acceptable to the gods than the most happy?
4. I will also relate what I heard respecting him from Hermogenes, the
son of Hipponicus, who said that after Meletus had laid the accusation
against him, he heard him speaking on any subject rather than that of his
trial, and remarked to him that he ought to consider what defense he should
make, but that he said at first, “Do I not appear to you to have passed
my whole life meditating on that subject?” and then, when he asked him
“How so?” he said that “he had gone through life doing nothing but considering
what was just and abstaining from what was unjust, which he conceived to
be the best meditation for his defense.” 5. Hermogenes said again, “Do
you not see, Socrates, that the judges at Athens have already put to death
many innocent persons, from being offended at their language, and have
allowed many that were guilty to escape?” “But, by Jupiter, Hermogenes,”
replied he, “when I was proceeding, a while ago, to study my address to
the judges, the daemon testified disapprobation.” “You say what is strange,”
rejoined Hermogenes. “And do you think it strange,” inquired Socrates,
“that it should seem better to the divinity that I should now close my
life? Do you not know, that, down to the present time, I would not admit
to any man that he has lived either better or with more pleasure than myself?
for I consider that those live best who study best to become as good as
possible; and that those live with most pleasure who feel the most assurance
that they are daily growing better and better. 7. This assurance I have
felt, to the present day, to be the case with respect to myself; and, associating
with other men, and comparing myself with others, I have always retained
this opinion respecting myself; and, not only I, but my friends also, maintain
a similar feeling with regard to me, not because they love me (for those
who love others may be thus affected towards the objects of their love),
but because they think that while they associated with me they became greatly
advanced in virtue. 8. If I shall live a longer period, perhaps I shall
be destined to sustain the evils of old age, to find my sight and hearing
weakened, to feel my intellect impaired, to become less apt to learn, and
more forgetful, and, in fine, to grow inferior to others in all those qualities
in which I was once superior to them. If I should be insensible to this
deterioration, life would not be worth retaining; and, if I should feel
it, how could I live otherwise than with less profit, and with less comfort?
9. If I am to die unjustly, my death will be a disgrace to those who unjustly
kill me; for if injustice is a disgrace, must it not be a disgrace to do
anything unjustly? But what disgrace will it be to me, that others could
not decide or act justly with regard to me? 10. Of the men who have lived
before me, I see that the estimation left among posterity with regard to
such as have done wrong, and such as have suffered wrong, is by no means
similar; and I know that I also, if I now die, shall obtain from mankind
far different consideration from that which they will receive who took
my life; for I know that they will always bear witness to me that I have
never wronged any man, or rendered any man less virtuous, but that I have
always endeavored to make those better who conversed with me.” Such discourse
he held with Hermogenes, and with others.
11. Of those who knew what sort of man Socrates was, such as were lovers of virtue, continue to regret him above all other men, even to the present day, as being most useful to them in their pursuit of virtue. To me, being such as I have described him, so pious that he did nothing without the sanction of the gods; so just, that he wronged no man even in the most trifling affair, but was of service, in the most important matters, to those who enjoyed his society; so temperate, that he never preferred pleasure to virtue; so wise, that he never erred in distinguishing better from worse, needing no counsel from others, but being sufficient in himself to discriminate between them; so able to explain and settle such questions by argument; and besides, so capable of discerning character, of confuting those who were in error, and of exhorting them to virtue and honor, he seemed to be such as the best and happiest of men would be. But if any one disapproves of my opinion, let him compare the conduct of others with that of Socrates, and determine accordingly.